SECTION I: OF THE DIFFERENT
SPECIES OF PHILOSOPHY.
MORAL philosophy, or the science of human
nature, may be treated after two different manners; each of which has its
peculiar merit, and may contribute to the entertainment, instruction, and
reformation of mankind. The one considers man chiefly as born for action;
and as influenced in his measures by taste and sentiment; pursuing one
object, and avoiding another, according to the value which these objects
seem to possess, and according to the light in which they present themselves.
As virtue, of all objects, is allowed to be the most valuable, this species
of philosophers paint her in the most amiable colours; borrowing all helps
from poetry and eloquence, and treating their subject in an easy and obvious
manner, and such as is best fitted to please the imagination, and engage
the affections. They select the most striking observations and instances
from common life; place opposite characters in a proper contrast; and alluring
us into the paths of virtue by the views of glory and happiness, direct
our steps in these paths by the soundest precepts and most illustrious
examples. They make us feel the difference between vice and virtue; they
excite and regulate our sentiments; and so they can but bend our hearts
to the love of probity and true honour, they think, that they have fully
attained the end of all their labours.
The other species of philosophers consider
man in the light of a reasonable rather than an active being, and endeavour
to form his understanding more than cultivate his manners. They regard
human nature as a subject of speculation; and with a narrow scrutiny examine
it, in order to find those principles, which regulate our understanding,
excite our sentiments, and make us approve or blame any particular object,
action, or behaviour. They think it a reproach to all literature, that
philosophy should not yet have fixed, beyond controversy, the foundation
of morals, reasoning, and criticism; and should for ever talk of truth
and falsehood, vice and virtue, beauty and deformity, without being able
to determine the source of these distinctions. While they attempt this
arduous task, they are deterred by no difficulties; but proceeding from
particular instances to general principles, they still push on their enquiries
to principles more general, and rest not satisfied till they arrive at
those original principles, by which, in every science, all human curiosity
must be bounded. Though their speculations seem abstract, and even unintelligible
to common readers, they aim at the approbation of the learned and the wise;
and think themselves sufficiently compensated for the labour of their whole
lives, if they can discover some hidden truths, which may contribute to
the instruction of posterity.
It is certain that the easy and obvious
philosophy will always, with the generality of mankind, have the preference
above the accurate and abstruse; and by many will be recommended, not only
as more agreeable, but more useful than the other. It enters more into
common life; moulds the heart and affections; and, by touching those principles
which actuate men, reforms their conduct, and brings them nearer to that
model of perfection which it describes. On the contrary, the abstruse philosophy,
being founded on a turn of mind, which cannot enter into business and action,
vanishes when the philosopher leaves the shade, and comes into open day;
nor can its principles easily retain any influence over our conduct and
behaviour. The feelings of our heart, the agitation of our passions, the
vehemence of our affections, dissipate all its conclusions, and reduce
the profound philosopher to a mere plebeian.
This also must be confessed, that the most
durable, as well as justest fame, has been acquired by the easy philosophy,
and that abstract reasoners seem hitherto to have enjoyed only a momentary
reputation, from the caprice or ignorance of their own age, but have not
been able to support their renown with more equitable posterity. It is
easy for a profound philosopher to commit a mistake in his subtle reasonings;
and one mistake is the necessary parent of another, while he pushes on
his consequences, and is not deterred from embracing any conclusion, by
its unusual appearance, or its contradiction to popular opinion. But a
philosopher, who purposes only to represent the common sense of mankind
in more beautiful and more engaging colours, if by accident he falls into
error, goes no farther; but renewing his appeal to common sense, and the
natural sentiments of the mind, returns into the right path, and secures
himself from any dangerous illusions. The fame of Cicero flourishes at
present; but that of Aristotle is utterly decayed. La Bruyere passes the
seas, and still maintains his reputation: but the glory of Malebranche
is confined to his own nation, and to his own age. And Addison, perhaps,
will be read with pleasure, when Locke shall be entirely forgotten.
The mere philosopher is a character, which
is commonly but little acceptable in the world, as being supposed to contribute
nothing either to the advantage or pleasure of society; while he lives
remote from communication with mankind, and is wrapped up in principles
and notions equally remote from their comprehension. On the other hand,
the mere ignorant is still more despised; nor is any thing deemed a surer
sign of an illiberal genius in an age and nation where the sciences flourish,
than to be entirely destitute of all relish for those noble entertainments.
The most perfect character is supposed to lie between those extremes; retaining
an equal ability and taste for books, company, and business; preserving
in conversation that discernment and delicacy which arise from polite letters;
and in business, that probity and accuracy which are the natural result
of a just philosophy. In order to diffuse and cultivate so accomplished
a character, nothing can be more useful than compositions of the easy style
and manner, which draw not too much from life, require no deep application
or retreat to be comprehended, and send back the student among mankind
full of noble sentiments and wise precepts, applicable to every exigence
of human life. By means of such compositions, virtue becomes amiable, science
agreeable, company instructive, and retirement entertaining.
Man is a reasonable being; and as such,
receives from science his proper food and nourishment: But so narrow are
the bounds of human understanding, that little satisfaction can be hoped
for in this particular, either from the extent of security or his acquisitions.
Man is a sociable, no less than a reasonable being: but neither can he
always enjoy company agreeable and amusing, or preserve the proper relish
for them. Man is also an active being; and from that disposition, as well
as from the various necessities of human life, must submit to business
and occupation: but the mind requires some relaxation, and cannot always
support its bent to care and industry. It seems, then, that nature has
pointed out a mixed kind of life as most suitable to the human race, and
secretly admonished them to allow none of these biases to draw too much,
so as to incapacitate them for other occupations and entertainments. Indulge
your passion for science, says she, but let your science be human, and
such as may have a direct reference to action and society. Abstruse thought
and profound researches I prohibit, and will severely punish, by the pensive
melancholy which they introduce, by the endless uncertainty in which they
involve you, and by the cold reception which your pretended discoveries
shall meet with, when communicated. Be a philosopher; but, amidst all your
philosophy, be still a man.
Were the generality of mankind contented
to prefer the easy philosophy to the abstract and profound, without throwing
any blame or contempt on the latter, it might not be improper, perhaps,
to comply with this general opinion, and allow every man to enjoy, without
opposition, his own taste and sentiment. But as the matter is often carried
farther, even to the absolute rejecting of all profound reasonings, or
what is commonly called metaphysics, we shall now proceed to consider what
can reasonably be pleaded in their behalf.
We may begin with observing, that one considerable
advantage, which results from the accurate and abstract philosophy, is,
its subserviency to the easy and humane; which, without the former, can
never attain a sufficient degree of exactness in its sentiments, precepts,
or reasonings. All polite letters are nothing but pictures of human life
in various attitudes and situations; and inspire us with different sentiments,
of praise or blame, admiration or ridicule, according to the qualities
of the object, which they set before us. An artist must be better qualified
to succeed in this undertaking, who, besides a delicate taste and a quick
apprehension, possesses an accurate knowledge of the internal fabric, the
operations of the understanding, the workings of the passions, and the
various species of sentiment which discriminate vice and virtue. How painful
soever this inward search or enquiry may appear, it becomes, in some measure,
requisite to those, who would describe with success the obvious and outward
appearances of life and manners. The anatomist presents to the eye the
most hideous and disagreeable objects; but his science is useful to the
painter in delineating even a Venus or an Helen. While the latter employs
all the richest colours of his art, and gives his figures the most graceful
and engaging airs; he must still carry his attention to the inward structure
of the human body, the position of the muscles, the fabric of the bones,
and the use and figure of every part or organ. Accuracy is, in every case,
advantageous to beauty, and just reasoning to delicate sentiment. In vain
would we exalt the one by depreciating the other.
Besides, we may observe, in every art or
profession, even those which most concern life or action, that a spirit
of accuracy, however acquired, carries all of them nearer their perfection,
and renders them more subservient to the interests of society. And though
a philosopher may live remote from business, the genius of philosophy,
if carefully cultivated by several, must gradually diffuse itself throughout
the whole society, and bestow a similar correctness on every art and calling.
The politician will acquire greater foresight and subtlety, in the subdividing
and balancing of power; the lawyer more method and finer principles in
his reasonings; and the general more regularity in his discipline, and
more caution in his plans and operations. The stability of modern governments
above the ancient, and the accuracy of modern philosophy, have improved,
and probably will still improve, by similar gradations.
Were there no advantage to be reaped from
these studies, beyond the gratification of an innocent curiosity, yet ought
not even this to be despised; as being one accession to those few safe
and harmless pleasures, which are bestowed on the human race. The sweetest
and most inoffensive path of life leads through the avenues of science
and learning; and whoever can either remove any obstructions in this way,
or open up any new prospect, ought so far to be esteemed a benefactor to
mankind. And though these researches may appear painful and fatiguing,
it is with some minds as with some bodies, which being endowed with vigorous
and florid health, require severe exercise, and reap a pleasure from what,
to the generality of mankind, may seem burdensome and laborious. Obscurity,
indeed, is painful to the mind as well as to the eye; but to bring light
from obscurity, by whatever labour, must needs be delightful and rejoicing.
But this obscurity in the profound and
abstract philosophy, is objected to, not only as painful and fatiguing,
but as the inevitable source of uncertainty and error. Here indeed lies
the justest and most plausible objection against a considerable part of
metaphysics, that they are not properly a science; but arise either from
the fruitless efforts of human vanity, which would penetrate into subjects
utterly inaccessible to the understanding, or from the craft of popular
superstitions, which, being unable to defend themselves on fair ground,
raise these intangling brambles to cover and protect their weakness. Chased
from the open country, these robbers fly into the forest, and lie in wait
to break in upon every unguarded avenue of the mind, and overwhelm it with
religious fears and prejudices. The stoutest antagonist, if he remit his
watch a moment, is oppressed. And many, through cowardice and folly, open
the gates to the enemies, and willingly receive them with reverence and
submission, as their legal sovereigns.
But is this a sufficient reason, why philosophers
should desist from such researches, and leave superstition still in possession
of her retreat? Is it not proper to draw an opposite conclusion, and perceive
the necessity of carrying the war into the most secret recesses of the
enemy? In vain do we hope, that men, from frequent disappointment, will
at last abandon such airy sciences, and discover the proper province of
human reason. For, besides, that many persons find too sensible an interest
in perpetually recalling such topics; besides this, I say, the motive of
blind despair can never reasonably have place in the sciences; since, however
unsuccessful former attempts may have proved, there is still room to hope,
that the industry, good fortune, or improved sagacity of succeeding generations
may reach discoveries unknown to former ages. Each adventurous genius will
still leap at the arduous prize, and find himself stimulated, rather than
discouraged, by the failures of his predecessors; while he hopes that the
glory of achieving so hard an adventure is reserved for him alone. The
only method of freeing learning, at once, from these abstruse questions,
is to enquire seriously into the nature of human understanding, and show,
from an exact analysis of its powers and capacity, that it is by no means
fitted for such remote and abstruse subjects. We must submit to this fatigue
in order to live at ease ever after: and must cultivate true metaphysics
with some care, in order to destroy the false and adulterate. Indolence,
which, to some persons, affords a safeguard against this deceitful philosophy,
is, with others, overbalanced by curiosity; and despair, which, at some
moments, prevails, may give place afterwards to sanguine hopes and expectations.
Accurate and just reasoning is the only catholic remedy, fitted for all
persons and all dispositions; and is alone able to subvert that abstruse
philosophy and metaphysical jargon, which being mixed up with popular superstition,
renders it in a manner impenetrable to careless reasoners, and gives it
the air of science and wisdom.
Besides this advantage of rejecting, after
deliberate enquiry, the most uncertain and disagreeable part of learning,
there are many positive advantages, which result from an accurate scrutiny
into the powers and faculties of human nature. It is remarkable concerning
the operations of the mind, that, though most intimately present to us,
yet, whenever they become the object of reflexion, they seem involved in
obscurity; nor can the eye readily find those lines and boundaries, which
discriminate and distinguish them. The objects are too fine to remain long
in the same aspect or situation; and must be apprehended in an instant,
by a superior penetration, derived from nature, and improved by habit and
reflexion. It becomes, therefore, no inconsiderable part of science barely
to know the different operations of the mind, to separate them from each
other, to class them under their proper heads, and to correct all that
seeming disorder, in which they lie involved, when made the object of reflexion
and enquiry. This talk of ordering and distinguishing, which has no merit,
when performed with regard to external bodies, the objects of our senses,
rises in its value, when directed towards the operations of the mind, in
proportion to the difficulty and labour, which we meet with in performing
it. And if we can go no farther than this mental geography, or delineation
of the distinct parts and powers of the mind, it is at least a satisfaction
to go so far; and the more obvious this science may appear (and it is by
no means obvious) the more contemptible still must the ignorance of it
be esteemed, in all pretenders to learning and philosophy.
Nor can there remain any suspicion, that
this science is uncertain and chimerical; unless we should entertain such
a scepticism as is entirely subversive of all speculation, and even action.
It cannot be doubted, that the mind is endowed with several powers and
faculties, that these powers are distinct from each other, that what is
really distinct to the immediate perception may be distinguished by reflexion;
and consequently, that there is a truth and falsehood in all propositions
on this subject, and a truth and falsehood, which lie not beyond the compass
of human understanding. There are many obvious distinctions of this kind,
such as those between the will and understanding, the imagination and passions,
which fall within the comprehension of every human creature; and the finer
and more philosophical distinctions are no less real and certain, though
more difficult to be comprehended. Some instances, especially late ones,
of success in these enquiries, may give us a juster notion of the certainty
and solidity of this branch of learning. And shall we esteem it worthy
the labour of a philosopher to give us a true system of the planets, and
adjust the position and order of those remote bodies; while we affect to
overlook those, who, with so much success, delineate the parts of the mind,
in which we are so intimately concerned?
But may we not hope, that philosophy, cultivated
with care, and encouraged by the attention of the public, may carry its
researches still farther, and discover, at least in some degree, the secret
springs and principles, by which the human mind is actuated in its operations?
Astronomers had long contented themselves with proving, from the phaenomena,
the true motions, order, and magnitude of the heavenly bodies: till a philosopher,
at last, arose, who seems, from the happiest reasoning, to have also determined
the laws and forces, by which the revolutions of the planets are governed
and directed. The like has been performed with regard to other parts of
nature. And there is no reason to despair of equal success in our enquiries
concerning the mental powers and economy, if prosecuted with equal capacity
and caution. It is probable, that one operation and principle of the mind
depends on another; which, again, may be resolved into one more general
and universal: and how far these researches may possibly be carried, it
will be difficult for us, before, or even after, a careful trial, exactly
to determine. This is certain, that attempts of this kind are every day
made even by those who philosophize the most negligently: and nothing can
be more requisite than to enter upon the enterprize with thorough care
and attention; that, if it lie within the compass of human understanding,
it may at last be happily achieved; if not, it may, however, be rejected
with some confidence and security. This last conclusion, surely, is not
desirable; nor ought it to be embraced too rashly. For how much must we
diminish from the beauty and value of this species of philosophy, upon
such a supposition? Moralists have hitherto been accustomed, when they
considered the vast multitude and diversity of those actions that excite
our approbation or dislike, to search for some common principle, on which
this variety of sentiments might depend. And though they have sometimes
carried the matter too far, by their passion for some one general principle;
it must, however, be confessed, that they are excusable in expecting to
find some general principles, into which all the vices and virtues were
justly to be resolved. The like has been the endeavour of critics, logicians,
and even politicians: nor have their attempts been wholly unsuccessful;
though perhaps longer time, greater accuracy, and more ardent application
may bring these sciences still nearer their perfection. To throw up at
once all pretensions of this kind may justly be deemed more rash, precipitate,
and dogmatical, than even the boldest and most affirmative philosophy,
that has ever attempted to impose its crude dictates and principles on
mankind.
What though these reasonings concerning
human nature seem abstract, and of difficult comprehension? This affords
no presumption of their falsehood. On the contrary, it seems impossible,
that what has hitherto escaped so many wise and profound philosophers can
be very obvious and easy. And whatever pains these researches may cost
us, we may think ourselves sufficiently rewarded, not only in point of
profit but of pleasure, if, by that means, we can make any addition to
our stock of knowledge, in subjects of such unspeakable importance.
But as, after all, the abstractedness of
these speculations is no recommendation, but rather a disadvantage to them,
and as this difficulty may perhaps be surmounted by care and art, and the
avoiding of all unnecessary detail, we have, in the following enquiry,
attempted to throw some light upon subjects, from which uncertainty has
hitherto deterred the wise, and obscurity the ignorant. Happy, if we can
unite the boundaries of the different species of philosophy, by reconciling
profound enquiry with clearness, and truth with novelty! And still more
happy, if, reasoning in this easy manner, we can undermine the foundations
of an abstruse philosophy, which seems to have hitherto served only as
a shelter to superstition, and a cover to absurdity and error!
SECTION II: OF THE ORIGIN
OF IDEAS
EVERY one will readily allow, that there is
a considerable difference between the perceptions of the mind, when a man
feels the pain of excessive heat, or the pleasure of moderate warmth, and
when he afterwards recalls to his memory this sensation, or anticipates
it by his imagination. These faculties may mimic or copy the perceptions
of the senses; but they never can entirely reach the force and vivacity
of the original sentiment. The utmost we say of them, even when they operate
with greatest vigour, is, that they represent their object in so lively
a manner, that we could almost say we feel or see it: But, except the mind
be disordered by disease or madness, they never can arrive at such a pitch
of vivacity, as to render these perceptions altogether undistinguishable.
All the colours of poetry, however splendid, can never paint natural objects
in such a manner as to make the description be taken for a real landskip.
The most lively thought is still inferior to the dullest sensation.
We may observe a like distinction to run
through all the other perceptions of the mind. A man in a fit of anger,
is actuated in a very different manner from one who only thinks of that
emotion. If you tell me, that any person is in love, I easily understand
your meaning, and from a just conception of his situation; but never can
mistake that conception for the real disorders and agitations of the passion.
When we reflect on our past sentiments and affections, our thought is a
faithful mirror, and copies its objects truly; but the colours which it
employs are faint and dull, in comparison of those in which our original
perceptions were clothed. It requires no nice discernment or metaphysical
head to mark the distinction between them.
Here therefore we may divide all the perceptions
of the mind into two classes or species, which are distinguished by their
different degrees of force and vivacity. The less forcible and lively are
commonly denominated Thoughts or Ideas. The other species want a name in
our language, and in most others; I suppose, because it was not requisite
for any, but philosophical purposes, to rank them under a general term
or appellation. Let us, therefore, use a little freedom, and call them
Impressions; employing that word in a sense somewhat different from the
usual. By the term impression, then, I mean all our more lively perceptions,
when we hear, or see, or feel, or love, or hate, or desire, or will. And
impressions are distinguished from ideas, which are the less lively perceptions,
of which we are conscious, when we reflect on any of those sensations or
movements above mentioned.
Nothing, at first view, may seem more unbounded
than the thought of man, which not only escapes all human power and authority,
but is not even restrained within the limits of nature and reality. To
form monsters, and join incongruous shapes and appearances, costs the imagination
no more trouble than to conceive the most natural and familiar objects.
And while the body is confined to one planet, along which it creeps with
pain and difficulty; the thought can in an instant transport us into the
most distant regions of the universe; or even beyond the universe, into
the unbounded chaos, where nature is supposed to lie in total confusion.
What never was seen, or heard of, may yet be conceived; nor is any thing
beyond the power of thought, except what implies an absolute contradiction.
But though our thought seems to possess
this unbounded liberty, we shall find, upon a nearer examination, that
it is really confined within very narrow limits, and that all this creative
power of the mind amounts to no more than the faculty of compounding, transposing,
augmenting, or diminishing the materials afforded us by the senses and
experience. When we think of a golden mountain, we only join two consistent
ideas, gold, and mountain, with which we were formerly acquainted. A virtuous
horse we can conceive; because, from our own feeling, we can conceive virtue;
and this we may unite to the figure and shape of a horse, which is an animal
familiar to us. In short, all the materials of thinking are derived either
from our outward or inward sentiment: the mixture and composition of these
belongs alone to the mind and will. Or, to express myself in philosophical
language, all our ideas or more feeble perceptions are copies of our impressions
or more lively ones.
To prove this, the two following arguments
will, I hope, be sufficient. First, when we analyze our thoughts or ideas,
however compounded or sublime, we always find that they resolve themselves
into such simple ideas as were copied from a precedent feeling or sentiment.
Even those ideas, which, at first view, seem the most wide of this origin,
are found, upon a nearer scrutiny, to be derived from it. The idea of God,
as meaning an infinitely intelligent, wise, and good Being, arises from
reflecting on the operations of our own mind, and augmenting, without limit,
those qualities of goodness and wisdom. We may prosecute this enquiry to
what length we please; where we shall always find, that every idea which
we examine is copied from a similar impression. Those who would assert
that this position is not universally true nor without exception, have
only one, and that an easy method of refuting it; by producing that idea,
which, in their opinion, is not derived from this source. It will then
be incumbent on us, if we would maintain our doctrine, to produce the impression,
or lively perception, which corresponds to it.
Secondly. If it happen, from a defect of
the organ, that a man is not susceptible of any species of sensation, we
always find that he is as little susceptible of the correspondent ideas.
A blind man can form no notion of colours; a deaf man of sounds. Restore
either of them that sense in which he is deficient; by opening this new
inlet for his sensations, you also open an inlet for the ideas; and he
finds no difficulty in conceiving these objects. The case is the same,
if the object, proper for exciting any sensation, has never been applied
to the organ. A Laplander or Negro has no notion of the relish of wine.
And though there are few or no instances of a like deficiency in the mind,
where a person has never felt or is wholly incapable of a sentiment or
passion that belongs to his species; yet we find the same observation to
take place in a less degree. A man of mild manners can form no idea of
inveterate revenge or cruelty; nor can a selfish heart easily conceive
the heights of friendship and generosity. It is readily allowed, that other
beings may possess many senses of which we can have no conception; because
the ideas of them have never been introduced to us in the only manner by
which an idea can have access to the mind, to wit, by the actual feeling
and sensation.
There is, however, one contradictory phenomenon,
which may prove that it is not absolutely impossible for ideas to arise,
independent of their correspondent impressions. I believe it will readily
be allowed, that the several distinct ideas of colour, which enter by the
eye, or those of sound, which are conveyed by the ear, are really different
from each other; though, at the same time, resembling. Now if this be true
of different colours, it must be no less so of the different shades of
the same colour; and each shade produces a distinct idea, independent of
the rest. For if this should be denied, it is possible, by the continual
gradation of shades, to run a colour insensibly into what is most remote
from it; and if you will not allow any of the means to be different, you
cannot, without absurdity, deny the extremes to be the same. Suppose, therefore,
a person to have enjoyed his sight for thirty years, and to have become
perfectly acquainted with colours of all kinds except one particular shade
of blue, for instance, which it never has been his fortune to meet with.
Let all the different shades of that colour, except that single one, be
placed before him, descending gradually from the deepest to the lightest;
it is plain that he will perceive a blank, where that shade is wanting,
and will be sensible that there is a greater distance in that place between
the contiguous colour than in any other. Now I ask, whether it be possible
for him, from his own imagination, to supply this deficiency, and raise
up to himself the idea of that particular shade, though it had never been
conveyed to him by his senses? I believe there are few but will be of opinion
that he can: and this may serve as a proof that the simple ideas are not
always, in every instance, derived from the correspondent impressions;
though this instance is so singular, that it is scarcely worth our observing,
and does not merit that for it alone we should alter our general maxim.
Here, therefore, is a proposition, which
not only seems, in itself, simple and intelligible; but, if a proper use
were made of it, might render every dispute equally intelligible, and banish
all that jargon, which has so long taken possession of metaphysical reasonings,
and drawn disgrace upon them. All ideas, especially abstract ones, are
naturally faint and obscure: the mind has but a slender hold of them: they
are apt to be confounded with other resembling ideas; and when we have
often employed any term, though without a distinct meaning, we are apt
to imagine it has a determinate idea annexed to it. On the contrary, all
impressions, that is, all sensations, either outward or inward, are strong
and vivid: the limits between them are more exactly determined: nor is
it easy to fall into any error or mistake with regard to them. When we
entertain, therefore, any suspicion that a philosophical term is employed
without any meaning or idea (as is but too frequent), we need but enquire,
from what impression is that supposed idea derived? And if it be impossible
to assign any, this will serve to confirm our suspicion. By bringing ideas
into so clear a light we may reasonably hope to remove all dispute, which
may arise, concerning their nature and reality.[1]
[1] It is probable that no more was meant
by these, who denied innate ideas, than that all ideas were copies of our
impressions; though it must be confessed, that the terms, which they employed,
were not chosen with such caution, nor so exactly defined, as to prevent
all mistakes about their doctrine. For what is meant by innate? If innate
be equivalent to natural, then all the perceptions and ideas of the mind
must be allowed to be innate or natural, in whatever sense we take the
latter word, whether in opposition to what is uncommon, artificial, or
miraculous. If by innate be meant, contemporary to our birth, the dispute
seems to be frivolous; nor is it worth while to enquire at what time thinking
begins, whether before, at, or after our birth. Again, the word idea, seems
to be commonly taken in a very loose sense, by LOCKE and others; as standing
for any of our perceptions, our sensations and passions, as well as thoughts.
Now in this sense, I should desire to know, what can be meant by asserting,
that selflove, or resentment of injuries, or the passion between the sexes
is not innate?
But admitting these terms, impressions
and ideas, in the sense above explained, and understanding by innate, what
is original or copied from no precedent perception, then may we assert
that all our impressions are innate, and our ideas not innate.
To be ingenuous, I must own it to be my
opinion, that LOCKE was betrayed into this question by the schoolmen, who,
making use of undefined terms, draw out their disputes to a tedious length,
without ever touching the point in question. A like ambiguity and circumlocution
seem to run through that philosopher's reasonings on this as well as most
other subjects.
SECTION III: OF THE
ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS
IT IS evident that there is a principle of
connexion between the different thoughts or ideas of the mind, and that
in their appearance to the memory or imagination, they introduce each other
with a certain degree of method and regularity. In our more serious thinking
or discourse this is so observable that any particular thought, which breaks
in upon the regular tract or chain of ideas, is immediately remarked and
rejected. And even in our wildest and most wandering reveries, nay in our
very dreams, we shall find, if we reflect, that the imagination ran not
altogether at adventures, but that there was still a connexion upheld among
the different ideas, which succeeded each other. Were the loosest and freest
conversation to be transcribed, there would immediately be observed something
which connected it in all its transitions. Or where this is wanting, the
person who broke the thread of discourse might still inform you, that there
had secretly revolved in his mind a succession of thought, which had gradually
led him from the subject of conversation. Among different languages, even
where we cannot suspect the least connexion or communication, it is found,
that the words, expressive of ideas, the most compounded, do yet nearly
correspond to each other: a certain proof that the simple ideas, comprehended
in the compound ones, were bound together by some universal principle,
which had an equal influence on all mankind.
Though it be too obvious to escape observation,
that different ideas are connected together; I do not find that any philosopher
has attempted to enumerate or class all the principles of association;
a subject, however, that seems worthy of curiosity. To me, there appear
to be only three principles of connexion among ideas, namely, Resemblance,
Contiguity in time or place, and Cause or Effect.
That these principles serve to connect
ideas will not, I believe, be much doubted. A picture naturally leads our
thoughts to the original:[1] the mention of one apartment in a building
naturally introduces an enquiry or discourse concerning the others:[2]
and if we think of a wound, we can scarcely forbear reflecting on the pain
which follows it.[3] But that this enumeration is complete, and that there
are no other principles of association except these, may be difficult to
prove to the satisfaction of the reader, or even to a man's own satisfaction.
All we can do, in such cases, is to run over several instances, and examine
carefully the principle which binds the different thoughts to each other,
never stopping till we render the principle as general as possible.[4]
The more instances we examine, and the more care we employ, the more assurance
shall we acquire, that the enumeration, which we form from the whole, is
complete and entire.
[1] Resemblance.
[2] Contiguity.
[3] Cause and effect.
[4] For instance, Contrast or Contrariety
is also a connexion among Ideas: but it may perhaps, be considered as a
mixture of Causation and Resemblance. Where two objects are contrary, the
one destroys the other; that is, the cause of its annihilation, and the
idea of the annihilation of an object, implies the idea of its former existence.
SECTION IV: SCEPTICAL
DOUBTS CONCERNING THE OPERATIONS OF THE UNDERSTANDING
PART I
ALL the objects of human reason or enquiry
may naturally be divided into two kinds, to wit, Relations of Ideas, and
Matters of Fact. Of the first kind are the sciences of Geometry, Algebra,
and Arithmetic; and in short, every affirmation which is either intuitively
or demonstratively certain. That the square of the hypothenuse is equal
to the square of the two sides, is a proposition which expresses a relation
between these figures. That three times five is equal to the half of thirty,
expresses a relation between these numbers. Propositions of this kind are
discoverable by the mere operation of thought, without dependence on what
is anywhere existent in the universe. Though there never were a circle
or triangle in nature, the truths demonstrated by Euclid would for ever
retain their certainty and evidence.
Matters of fact, which are the second objects
of human reason, are not ascertained in the same manner; nor is our evidence
of their truth, however great, of a like nature with the foregoing. The
contrary of every matter of fact is still possible; because it can never
imply a contradiction, and is conceived by the mind with the same facility
and distinctness, as if ever so conformable to reality. That the sun will
not rise to-morrow is no less intelligible a proposition, and implies no
more contradiction than the affirmation, that it will rise. We should in
vain, therefore, attempt to demonstrate its falsehood. Were it demonstratively
false, it would imply a contradiction, and could never be distinctly conceived
by the mind.
It may, therefore, be a subject worthy
of curiosity, to enquire what is the nature of that evidence which assures
us of any real existence and matter of fact, beyond the present testimony
of our senses, or the records of our memory. This part of philosophy, it
is observable, has been little cultivated, either by the ancients or moderns;
and therefore our doubts and errors, in the prosecution of so important
an enquiry, may be the more excusable; while we march through such difficult
paths without any guide or direction. They may even prove useful, by exciting
curiosity, and destroying that implicit faith and security, which is the
bane of all reasoning and free enquiry. The discovery of defects in the
common philosophy, if any such there be, will not, I presume, be a discouragement,
but rather an incitement, as is usual, to attempt something more full and
satisfactory than has yet been proposed to the public.
All reasonings concerning matter of fact
seem to be founded on the relation of Cause and Effect. By means of that
relation alone we can go beyond the evidence of our memory and senses.
If you were to ask a man, why he believes any matter of fact, which is
absent; for instance, that his friend is in the country, or in France;
he would give you a reason; and this reason would be some other fact; as
a letter received from him, or the knowledge of his former resolutions
and promises. A man finding a watch or any other machine in a desert island,
would conclude that there had once been men in that island. All our reasonings
concerning fact are of the same nature. And here it is constantly supposed
that there is a connexion between the present fact and that which is inferred
from it. Were there nothing to bind them together, the inference would
be entirely precarious. The hearing of an articulate voice and rational
discourse in the dark assures us of the presence of some person: Why? because
these are the effects of the human make and fabric, and closely connected
with it. If we anatomize all the other reasonings of this nature, we shall
find that they are founded on the relation of cause and effect, and that
this relation is either near or remote, direct or collateral. Heat and
light are collateral effects of fire, and the one effect may justly be
inferred from the other.
If we would satisfy ourselves, therefore,
concerning the nature of that evidence, which assures us of matters of
fact, we must enquire how we arrive at the knowledge of cause and effect.
I shall venture to affirm, as a general
proposition, which admits of no exception, that the knowledge of this relation
is not, in any instance, attained by reasonings a priori; but arises entirely
from experience, when we find that any particular objects are constantly
conjoined with each other. Let an object be presented to a man of ever
so strong natural reason and abilities; if that object be entirely new
to him, he will not be able, by the most accurate examination of its sensible
qualities, to discover any of its causes or effects. Adam, though his rational
faculties be supposed, at the very first, entirely perfect, could not have
inferred from the fluidity and transparency of water that it would suffocate
him, or from the light and warmth of fire that it would consume him. No
object ever discovers, by the qualities which appear to the senses, either
the causes which produced it, or the effects which will arise from it;
nor can our reason, unassisted by experience, ever draw any inference concerning
real existence and matter of fact.
This proposition, that causes and effects
are discoverable, not by reason but by experience, will readily be admitted
with regard to such objects, as we remember to have once been altogether
unknown to us; since we must be conscious of the utter inability, which
we then lay under, of foretelling what would arise from them. Present two
smooth pieces of marble to a man who has no tincture of natural philosophy;
he will never discover that they will adhere together in such a manner
as to require great force to separate them in a direct line, while they
make so small a resistance to a lateral pressure. Such events, as bear
little analogy to the common course of nature, are also readily confessed
to be known only by experience; nor does any man imagine that the explosion
of gunpowder, or the attraction of a loadstone, could ever be discovered
by arguments a priori. In like manner, when an effect is supposed to depend
upon an intricate machinery or secret structure of parts, we make no difficulty
in attributing all our knowledge of it to experience. Who will assert that
he can give the ultimate reason, why milk or bread is proper nourishment
for a man, not for a lion or a tiger?
But the same truth may not appear, at first
sight, to have the same evidence with regard to events, which have become
familiar to us from our first appearance in the world, which bear a close
analogy to the whole course of nature, and which are supposed to depend
on the simple qualities of objects, without any secret structure of parts.
We are apt to imagine that we could discover these effects by the mere
operation of our reason, without experience. We fancy, that were we brought
on a sudden into this world, we could at first have inferred that one Billiard-ball
would communicate motion to another upon impulse; and that we needed not
to have waited for the event, in order to pronounce with certainty concerning
it. Such is the influence of custom, that, where it is strongest, it not
only covers our natural ignorance, but even conceals itself, and seems
not to take place, merely because it is found in the highest degree.
But to convince us that all the laws of
nature, and all the operations of bodies without exception, are known only
by experience, the following reflections may, perhaps, suffice. Were any
object presented to us, and were we required to pronounce concerning the
effect, which will result from it, without consulting past observation;
after what manner, I beseech you, must the mind proceed in this operation?
It must invent or imagine some event, which it ascribes to the object as
its effect; and it is plain that this invention must be entirely arbitrary.
The mind can never possibly find the effect in the supposed cause, by the
most accurate scrutiny and examination. For the effect is totally different
from the cause, and consequently can never be discovered in it. Motion
in the second Billiard-ball is a quite distinct event from motion in the
first; nor is there anything in the one to suggest the smallest hint of
the other. A stone or piece of metal raised into the air, and left without
any support, immediately falls: but to consider the matter a priori, is
there anything we discover in this situation which can beget the idea of
a downward, rather than an upward, or any other motion, in the stone or
metal?
And as the first imagination or invention
of a particular effect, in all natural operations, is arbitrary, where
we consult not experience; so must we also esteem the supposed tie or connexion
between the cause and effect, which binds them together, and renders it
impossible that any other effect could result from the operation of that
cause. When I see, for instance, a Billiard-ball moving in a straight line
towards another; even suppose motion in the second ball should by accident
be suggested to me, as the result of their contact or impulse; may I not
conceive, that a hundred different events might as well follow from that
cause? May not both these balls remain at absolute rest? May not the first
ball return in a straight line, or leap off from the second in any line
or direction? All these suppositions are consistent and conceivable. Why
then should we give the preference to one, which is no more consistent
or conceivable than the rest? All our reasonings a priori will never be
able to show us any foundation for this preference.
In a word, then, every effect is a distinct
event from its cause. It could not, therefore, be discovered in the cause,
and the first invention or conception of it, a priori, must be entirely
arbitrary. And even after it is suggested, the conjunction of it with the
cause must appear equally arbitrary; since there are always many other
effects, which, to reason, must seem fully as consistent and natural. In
vain, therefore, should we pretend to determine any single event, or infer
any cause or effect, without the assistance of observation and experience.
Hence we may discover the reason why no
philosopher, who is rational and modest, has ever pretended to assign the
ultimate cause of any natural operation, or to show distinctly the action
of that power, which produces any single effect in the universe. It is
confessed, that the utmost effort of human reason is to reduce the principles,
productive of natural phenomena, to a greater simplicity, and to resolve
the many particular effects into a few general causes, by means of reasonings
from analogy, experience, and observation. But as to the causes of these
general causes, we should in vain attempt their discovery; nor shall we
ever be able to satisfy ourselves, by any particular explication of them.
These ultimate springs and principles are totally shut up from human curiosity
and enquiry. Elasticity, gravity, cohesion of parts, communication of motion
by impulse; these are probably the ultimate causes and principles which
we shall ever discover in nature; and we may esteem ourselves sufficiently
happy, if, by accurate enquiry and reasoning, we can trace up the particular
phenomena to, or near to, these general principles. The most perfect philosophy
of the natural kind only staves off our ignorance a little longer: as perhaps
the most perfect philosophy of the moral or metaphysical kind serves only
to discover larger portions of it. Thus the observation of human blindness
and weakness is the result of all philosophy, and meets us at every turn,
in spite of our endeavours to elude or avoid it.
Nor is geometry, when taken into the assistance
of natural philosophy, ever able to remedy this defect, or lead us into
the knowledge of ultimate causes, by all that accuracy of reasoning for
which it is so justly celebrated. Every part of mixed mathematics proceeds
upon the supposition that certain laws are established by nature in her
operations; and abstract reasonings are employed, either to assist experience
in the discovery of these laws, or to determine their influence in particular
instances, where it depends upon any precise degree of distance and quantity.
Thus, it is a law of motion, discovered by experience, that the moment
or force of any body in motion is in the compound ratio or proportion of
its solid contents and its velocity; and consequently, that a small force
may remove the greatest obstacle or raise the greatest weight, if, by any
contrivance or machinery, we can increase the velocity of that force, so
as to make it an overmatch for its antagonist. Geometry assists us in the
application of this law, by giving us the just dimensions of all the parts
and figures which can enter into any species of machine; but still the
discovery of the law itself is owing merely to experience, and all the
abstract reasonings in the world could never lead us one step towards the
knowledge of it. When we reason a priori, and consider merely any object
or cause, as it appears to the mind, independent of all observation, it
never could suggest to us the notion of any distinct object, such as its
effect; much less, show us the inseparable and inviolable connexion between
them. A man must be very sagacious who could discover by reasoning that
crystal is the effect of heat, and ice of cold, without being previously
acquainted with the operation of these qualities.
PART II
BUT we have not yet attained any tolerable
satisfaction with regard to the question first proposed. Each solution
still gives rise to a new question as difficult as the foregoing, and leads
us on to farther enquiries. When it is asked, What is the nature of all
our reasonings concerning matter of fact? the proper answer seems to be,
that they are founded on the relation of cause and effect. When again it
is asked, What is the foundation of all our reasonings and conclusions
concerning that relation? it may be replied in one word, Experience. But
if we still carry on our sifting humour, and ask, What is the foundation
of all conclusions from experience? this implies a new question, which
may be of more difficult solution and explication. Philosophers, that give
themselves airs of superior wisdom and sufficiency, have a hard task when
they encounter persons of inquisitive dispositions, who push them from
every corner to which they retreat, and who are sure at last to bring them
to some dangerous dilemma. The best expedient to prevent this confusion,
is to be modest in our pretensions; and even to discover the difficulty
ourselves before it is objected to us. By this means, we may make a kind
of merit of our very ignorance.
I shall content myself, in this section,
with an easy task, and shall pretend only to give a negative answer to
the question here proposed. I say then, that, even after we have experience
of the operations of cause and effect, our conclusions from that experience
are not founded on reasoning, or any process of the understanding. This
answer we must endeavour both to explain and to defend.
It must certainly be allowed, that nature
has kept us at a great distance from all her secrets, and has afforded
us only the knowledge of a few superficial qualities of objects; while
she conceals from us those powers and principles on which the influence
of those objects entirely depends. Our senses inform us of the colour,
weight, and consistence of bread; but neither sense nor reason can ever
inform us of those qualities which fit it for the nourishment and support
of a human body. Sight or feeling conveys an idea of the actual motion
of bodies; but as to that wonderful force or power, which would carry on
a moving body for ever in a continued change of place, and which bodies
never lose but by communicating it to others; of this we cannot form the
most distant conception. But notwithstanding this ignorance of natural
powers[1] and principles, we always presume, when we see like sensible
qualities, that they have like secret powers, and expect that effects,
similar to those which we have experienced, will follow from them. If a
body of like colour and consistence with that bread, which we have formerly
eat, be presented to us, we make no scruple of repeating the experiment,
and foresee, with certainty, like nourishment and support. Now this is
a process of the mind or thought, of which I would willingly know the foundation.
It is allowed on all hands that there is no known connexion between the
sensible qualities and the secret powers; and consequently, that the mind
is not led to form such a conclusion concerning their constant and regular
conjunction, by anything which it knows of their nature. As to past Experience,
it can be allowed to give direct and certain information of those precise
objects only, and that precise period of time, which fell under its cognizance:
but why this experience should be extended to future times, and to other
objects, which for aught we know, may be only in appearance similar; this
is the main question on which I would insist. The bread, which I formerly
eat, nourished me; that is, a body of such sensible qualities was, at that
time, endued with such secret powers: but does it follow, that other bread
must also nourish me at another time, and that like sensible qualities
must always be attended with like secret powers? The consequence seems
nowise necessary. At least, it must be acknowledged that there is here
a consequence drawn by the mind; that there is a certain step taken; a
process of thought, and an inference, which wants to be explained. These
two propositions are far from being the same. I have found that such an
object has always been attended with such an effect, and I foresee, that
other objects, which are, in appearance, similar, will be attended with
similar effects. I shall allow, if you please, that the one proposition
may justly be inferred from the other: I know, in fact, that it always
is inferred. But if you insist that the inference is made by a chain of
reasoning, I desire you to produce that reasoning. The connexion between
these propositions is not intuitive. There is required a medium, which
may enable the mind to draw such an inference, if indeed it be drawn by
reasoning and argument. What that medium is, I must confess, passes my
comprehension; and it is incumbent on those to produce it, who assert that
it really exists, and is the origin of all our conclusions concerning matter
of fact.
This negative argument must certainly,
in process of time, become altogether convincing, if many penetrating and
able philosophers shall turn their enquiries this way and no one be ever
able to discover any connecting proposition or intermediate step, which
supports the understanding in this conclusion. But as the question is yet
new, every reader may not trust so far to his own penetration, as to conclude,
because an argument escapes his enquiry, that therefore it does not really
exist. For this reason it may be requisite to venture upon a more difficult
task; and enumerating all the branches of human knowledge, endeavour to
show that none of them can afford such an argument.
All reasonings may be divided into two
kinds, namely, demonstrative reasoning, or that concerning relations of
ideas, and moral reasoning, or that concerning matter of fact and existence.
That there are no demonstrative arguments in the case seems evident; since
it implies no contradiction that the course of nature may change, and that
an object, seemingly like those which we have experienced, may be attended
with different or contrary effects. May I not clearly and distinctly conceive
that a body, falling from the clouds, and which, in all other respects,
resembles snow, has yet the taste of salt or feeling of fire? Is there
any more intelligible proposition than to affirm, that all the trees will
flourish in December and January, and decay in May and June? Now whatever
is intelligible, and can be distinctly conceived, implies no contradiction,
and can never be proved false by any demonstrative argument or abstract
reasoning a priori.
If we be, therefore, engaged by arguments
to put trust in past experience, and make it the standard of our future
judgment, these arguments must be probable only, or such as regard matter
of fact and real existence according to the division above mentioned. But
that there is no argument of this kind, must appear, if our explication
of that species of reasoning be admitted as solid and satisfactory. We
have said that all arguments concerning existence are founded on the relation
of cause and effect; that our knowledge of that relation is derived entirely
from experience; and that all our experimental conclusions proceed upon
the supposition that the future will be conformable to the past. To endeavour,
therefore, the proof of this last supposition by probable arguments, or
arguments regarding existence, must be evidently going in a circle, and
taking that for granted, which is the very point in question.
In reality, all arguments from experience
are founded on the similarity which we discover among natural objects,
and by which we are induced to expect effects similar to those which we
have found to follow from such objects. And though none but a fool or madman
will ever pretend to dispute the authority of experience, or to reject
that great guide of human life, it may surely be allowed a philosopher
to have so much curiosity at least as to examine the principle of human
nature, which gives this mighty authority to experience, and makes us draw
advantage from that similarity which nature has placed among different
objects. From causes which appear similar we expect similar effects. This
is the sum of all our experimental conclusions. Now it seems evident that,
if this conclusion were formed by reason, it would be as perfect at first,
and upon one instance, as after ever so long a course of experience. But
the case is far otherwise. Nothing so like as eggs; yet no one, on account
of this appearing similarity, expects the same taste and relish in all
of them. It is only after a long course of uniform experiments in any kind,
that we attain a firm reliance and security with regard to a particular
event. Now where is that process of reasoning which, from one instance,
draws a conclusion, so different from that which it infers from a hundred
instances that are nowise different from that single one? This question
I propose as much for the sake of information, as with an intention of
raising difficulties. I cannot find, I cannot imagine any such reasoning.
But I keep my mind still open to instruction, if any one will vouchsafe
to bestow it on me.
Should it be said that, from a number of
uniform experiments, we infer a connexion between the sensible qualities
and the secret powers; this, I must confess, seems the same difficulty,
couched in different terms. The question still recurs, on what process
of argument this inference is founded? Where is the medium, the interposing
ideas, which join propositions so very wide of each other? It is confessed
that the colour, consistence, and other sensible qualities of bread appear
not, of themselves, to have any connexion with the secret powers of nourishment
and support. For otherwise we could infer these secret powers from the
first appearance of these sensible qualities, without the aid of experience;
contrary to the sentiment of all philosophers, and contrary to plain matter
of fact. Here, then, is our natural state of ignorance with regard to the
powers and influence of all objects. How is this remedied by experience?
It only shows us a number of uniform effects, resulting from certain objects,
and teaches us that those particular objects, at that particular time,
were endowed with such powers and forces. When a new object, endowed with
similar sensible qualities, is produced, we expect similar powers and forces,
and look for a like effect. >From a body of like colour and consistence
with bread we expect like nourishment and support. But this surely is a
step or progress of the mind, which wants to be explained. When a man says,
I have found, in all past instances, such sensible qualities conjoined
with such secret powers: And when he says, Similar sensible qualities will
always be conjoined with similar secret powers, he is not guilty of a tautology,
nor are these propositions in any respect the same. You say that the one
proposition is an inference from the other. But you must confess that the
inference is not intuitive; neither is it demonstrative: Of what nature
is it, then? To say it is experimental, is begging the question. For all
inferences from experience suppose, as their foundation, that the future
will resemble the past, and that similar powers will be conjoined with
similar sensible qualities. If there be any suspicion that the course of
nature may change, and that the past may be no rule for the future, all
experience becomes useless, and can give rise to no inference or conclusion.
It is impossible, therefore, that any arguments from experience can prove
this resemblance of the past to the future; since all these arguments are
founded on the supposition of that resemblance. Let the course of things
be allowed hitherto ever so regular; that alone, without some new argument
or inference, proves not that, for the future, it will continue so. In
vain do you pretend to have learned the nature of bodies from your past
experience. Their secret nature, and consequently all their effects and
influence, may change, without any change in their sensible qualities.
This happens sometimes, and with regard to some objects: Why may it not
happen always, and with regard to all objects? What logic, what process
or argument secures you against this supposition? My practice, you say,
refutes my doubts. But you mistake the purport of my question. As an agent,
I am quite satisfied in the point; but as a philosopher, who has some share
of curiosity, I will not say scepticism, I want to learn the foundation
of this inference. No reading, no enquiry has yet been able to remove my
difficulty, or give me satisfaction in a matter of such importance. Can
I do better than propose the difficulty to the public, even though, perhaps,
I have small hopes of obtaining a solution? We shall at least, by this
means, be sensible of our ignorance, if we do not augment our knowledge.
I must confess that a man is guilty of
unpardonable arrogance who concludes, because an argument has escaped his
own investigation, that therefore it does not really exist. I must also
confess that, though all the learned, for several ages, should have employed
themselves in fruitless search upon any subject, it may still, perhaps,
be rash to conclude positively that the subject must, therefore, pass all
human comprehension. Even though we examine all the sources of our knowledge,
and conclude them unfit for such a subject, there may still remain a suspicion,
that the enumeration is not complete, or the examination not accurate.
But with regard to the present subject, there are some considerations which
seem to remove all this accusation of arrogance or suspicion of mistake.
It is certain that the most ignorant and
stupid peasants-nay infants, nay even brute beasts--improve by experience,
and learn the qualities of natural objects, by observing the effects which
result from them. When a child has felt the sensation of pain from touching
the flame of a candle, he will be careful not to put his hand near any
candle; but will expect a similar effect from a cause which is similar
in its sensible qualities and appearance. If you assert, therefore, that
the understanding of the child is led into this conclusion by any process
of argument or ratiocination, I may justly require you to produce that
argument; nor have you any pretence to refuse so equitable a demand. You
cannot say that the argument is abstruse, and may possibly escape your
enquiry; since you confess that it is obvious to the capacity of a mere
infant. If you hesitate, therefore, a moment, or if, after reflection,
you produce any intricate or profound argument, you, in a manner, give
up the question, and confess that it is not reasoning which engages us
to suppose the past resembling the future, and to expect similar effects
from causes which are, to appearance, similar. This is the proposition
which I intended to enforce in the present section. If I be right, I pretend
not to have made any mighty discovery. And if I be wrong, I must acknowledge
myself to be indeed a very backward scholar; since I cannot now discover
an argument which, it seems, was perfectly familiar to me long before I
was out of my cradle.
[1] The word, Power, is here used in a
loose and popular sense. The more accurate explication of it would give
additional evidence to this argument. See Sect. 7.
SECTION V: SCEPTICAL
SOLUTION OF THESE DOUBTS
PART I
THE passion for philosophy, like that for
religion, seems liable to this inconvenience, that, though it aims at the
correction of our manners, and extirpation of our vices, it may only serve,
by imprudent management, to foster a predominant inclination, and push
the mind, with more determined resolution, towards that side which already
draws too much, by the bias and propensity of the natural temper. It is
certain that, while we aspire to the magnanimous firmness of the philosophic
sage, and endeavour to confine our pleasures altogether within our own
minds, we may, at last, render our philosophy like that of Epictetus, and
other Stoics, only a more refined system of selfishness, and reason ourselves
out of all virtue as well as social enjoyment. While we study with attention
the vanity of human life, and turn all our thoughts towards the empty and
transitory nature of riches and honours, we are, perhaps, all the while
flattering our natural indolence, which, hating the bustle of the world,
and drudgery of business, seeks a pretence of reason to give itself a full
and uncontrolled indulgence. There is, however, one species of philosophy
which seems little liable to this inconvenience, and that because it strikes
in with no disorderly passion of the human mind, nor can mingle itself
with any natural affection or propensity; and that is the Academic or Sceptical
philosophy. The academics always talk of doubt and suspense of judgment,
of danger in hasty determinations, of confining to very narrow bounds the
enquiries of the understanding, and of renouncing all speculations which
lie not within the limits of common life and practice. Nothing, therefore,
can be more contrary than such a philosophy to the supine indolence of
the mind, its rash arrogance, its lofty pretensions, and its superstitious
credulity. Every passion is mortified by it, except the love of truth;
and that passion never is, nor can be, carried to too high a degree. It
is surprising, therefore, that this philosophy, which, in almost every
instance, must be harmless and innocent, should be the subject of so much
groundless reproach and obloquy. But, perhaps, the very circumstance which
renders it so innocent is what chiefly exposes it to the public hatred
and resentment. By flattering no irregular passion, it gains few partizans:
By opposing so many vices and follies, it raises to itself abundance of
enemies, who stigmatize it as libertine, profane, and irreligious.
Nor need we fear that this philosophy,
while it endeavours to limit our enquiries to common life, should ever
undermine the reasonings of common life, and carry its doubts so far as
to destroy all action, as well as speculation. Nature will always maintain
her rights, and prevail in the end over any abstract reasoning whatsoever.
Though we should conclude, for instance, as in the foregoing section, that,
in all reasonings from experience, there is a step taken by the mind which
is not supported by any argument or process of the understanding; there
is no danger that these reasonings, on which almost all knowledge depends,
will ever be affected by such a discovery. If the mind be not engaged by
argument to make this step, it must be induced by some other principle
of equal weight and authority; and that principle will preserve its influence
as long as human nature remains the same. What that principle is may well
be worth the pains of enquiry.
Suppose a person, though endowed with the
strongest faculties of reason and reflection, to be brought on a sudden
into this world; he would, indeed, immediately observe a continual succession
of objects, and one event following another; but he would not be able to
discover anything farther. He would not, at first, by any reasoning, be
able to reach the idea of cause and effect; since the particular powers,
by which all natural operations are performed, never appear to the senses;
nor is it reasonable to conclude, merely because one event, in one instance,
precedes another, that therefore the one is the cause, the other the effect.
Their conjunction may be arbitrary and casual. There may be no reason to
infer the existence of one from the appearance of the other. And in a word,
such a person, without more experience, could never employ his conjecture
or reasoning concerning any matter of fact, or be assured of anything beyond
what was immediately present to his memory and senses.
Suppose, again, that he has acquired more
experience, and has lived so long in the world as to have observed familiar
objects or events to be constantly conjoined together; what is the consequence
of this experience? He immediately infers the existence of one object from
the appearance of the other. Yet he has not, by all his experience, acquired
any idea or knowledge of the secret power by which the one object produces
the other; nor is it by any process of reasoning, he is engaged to draw
this inference. But still he finds himself determined to draw it: and though
he should be convinced that his understanding has no part in the operation,
he would nevertheless continue in the same course of thinking. There is
some other principle which determines him to form such a conclusion.
This principle is Custom or Habit. For
wherever the repetition of any particular act or operation produces a propensity
to renew the same act or operation, without being impelled by any reasoning
or process of the understanding, we always say, that this propensity is
the effect of Custom. By employing that word, we pretend not to have given
the ultimate reason of such a propensity. We only point out a principle
of human nature, which is universally acknowledged, and which is well known
by its effects. Perhaps we can push our enquiries no farther, or pretend
to give the cause of this cause; but must rest contented with it as the
ultimate principle, which we can assign, of all our conclusions from experience.
It is sufficient satisfaction, that we can go so far, without repining
at the narrowness of our faculties because they will carry us no farther.
And it is certain we here advance a very intelligible proposition at least,
if not a true one, when we assert that, after the constant conjunction
of two objects--heat and flame, for instance, weight and solidity-we are
determined by custom alone to expect the one from the appearance of the
other. This hypothesis seems even the only one which explains the difficulty,
why we draw, from a thousand instances, an inference which we are not able
to draw from one instance, that is, in no respect, different from them.
Reason is incapable of any such variation. The conclusions which it draws
from considering one circle are the same which it would form upon surveying
all the circles in the universe. But no man, having seen only one body
move after being impelled by another, could infer that every other body
will move after a like impulse. All inferences from experience, therefore,
are effects of custom, not of reasoning.[1]
Custom, then, is the great guide of human
life. It is that principle alone which renders our experience useful to
us, and makes us expect, for the future, a similar train of events with
those which have appeared in the past. Without the influence of custom,
we should be entirely ignorant of every matter of fact beyond what is immediately
present to the memory and senses. We should never know how to adjust means
to ends, or to employ our natural powers in the production of any effect.
There would be an end at once of all action, as well as of the chief part
of speculation.
But here it may be proper to remark, that
though our conclusions from experience carry us beyond our memory and senses,
and assure us of matters of fact which happened in the most distant places
and most remote ages, yet some fact must always be present to the senses
or memory, from which we may first proceed in drawing these conclusions.
A man, who should find in a desert country the remains of pompous buildings,
would conclude that the country had, in ancient times, been cultivated
by civilized inhabitants; but did nothing of this nature occur to him,
he could never form such an inference. We learn the events of former ages
from history; but then we must peruse the volumes in which this instruction
is contained, and thence carry up our inferences from one testimony to
another, till we arrive at the eyewitnesses and spectators of these distant
events. In a word, if we proceed not upon some fact, present to the memory
or senses, our reasonings would be merely hypothetical; and however the
particular links might be connected with each other, the whole chain of
inferences would have nothing to support it, nor could we ever, by its
means, arrive at the knowledge of any real existence. If I ask why you
believe any particular matter of fact, which you relate, you must tell
me some reason; and this reason will be some other fact, connected with
it. But as you cannot proceed after this manner, in infinitum, you must
at last terminate in some fact, which is present to your memory or senses;
or must allow that your belief is entirely without foundation.
What, then, is the conclusion of the whole
matter? A simple one; though, it must be confessed, pretty remote from
the common theories of philosophy. All belief of matter of fact or real
existence is derived merely from some object, present to the memory or
senses, and a customary conjunction between that and some other object.
Or in other words; having found, in many instances, that any two kinds
of objects--flame and heat, snow and cold--have always been conjoined together;
if flame or snow be presented anew to the senses, the mind is carried by
custom to expect heat or cold, and to believe that such a quality does
exist, and will discover itself upon a nearer approach. This belief is
the necessary result of placing the mind in such circumstances. It is an
operation of the soul, when we are so situated, as unavoidable as to feel
the passion of love, when we receive benefits; or hatred, when we meet
with injuries. All these operations are a species of natural instincts,
which no reasoning or process of the thought and understanding is able
either to produce or to prevent.
At this point, it would be very allowable
for us to stop our philosophical researches. In most questions we can never
make a single step farther; and in all questions we must terminate here
at last, after our most restless and curious enquiries. But still our curiosity
will be pardonable, perhaps commendable, if it carry us on to still farther
researches, and make us examine more accurately the nature of this belief,
and of the customary conjunction, whence it is derived. By this means we
may meet with some explications and analogies that will give satisfaction;
at least to such as love the abstract sciences, and can be entertained
with speculations, which, however accurate, may still retain a degree of
doubt and uncertainty. As to readers of a different taste; the remaining
part of this section is not calculated for them, and the following enquiries
may well be understood, though it be neglected.
PART II
NOTHING is more free than the imagination
of man; and though it cannot exceed that original stock of ideas furnished
by the internal and external senses, it has unlimited power of mixing,
compounding, separating, and dividing these ideas, in all the varieties
of fiction and vision. It can feign a train of events, with all the appearance
of reality, ascribe to them a particular time and place, conceive them
as existent, and paint them out to itself with every circumstance, that
belongs to any historical fact, which it believes with the greatest certainty.
Wherein, therefore, consists the difference between such a fiction and
belief? It lies not merely in any peculiar idea, which is annexed to such
a conception as commands our assent, and which is wanting to every known
fiction. For as the mind has authority over all its ideas, it could voluntarily
annex this particular idea to any fiction, and consequently be able to
believe whatever it pleases; contrary to what we find by daily experience.
We can, in our conception, join the head of a man to the body of a horse;
but it is not in our power to believe that such an animal has ever really
existed.
It follows, therefore, that the difference
between fiction and belief lies in some sentiment or feeling, which is
annexed to the latter, not to the former, and which depends not on the
will, nor can be commanded at pleasure. It must be excited by nature, like
all other sentiments; and must arise from the particular situation, in
which the mind is placed at any particular juncture. Whenever any object
is presented to the memory or senses, it immediately, by the force of custom,
carries the imagination to conceive that object, which is usually conjoined
to it; and this conception is attended with a feeling or sentiment, different
from the loose reveries of the fancy. In this consists the whole nature
of belief. For as there is no matter of fact which we believe so firmly
that we cannot conceive the contrary, there would be no difference between
the conception assented to and that which is rejected, were it not for
some sentiment which distinguishes the one from the other. If I see a billiard-ball
moving toward another, on a smooth table, I can easily conceive it to stop
upon contact. This conception implies no contradiction; but still it feels
very differently from that conception by which I represent to myself the
impulse and the communication of motion from one ball to another.
Were we to attempt a definition of this
sentiment, we should, perhaps, find it a very difficult, if not an impossible
task; in the same manner as if we should endeavour to define the feeling
of cold or passion of anger, to a creature who never had any experience
of these sentiments. Belief is the true and proper name of this feeling;
and no one is ever at a loss to know the meaning of that term; because
every man is every moment conscious of the sentiment represented by it.
It may not, however, be improper to attempt a description of this sentiment;
in hopes we may, by that means, arrive at some analogies, which may afford
a more perfect explication of it. I say, then, that belief is nothing but
a more vivid, lively, forcible, firm, steady conception of an object, than
what the imagination alone is ever able to attain. This variety of terms,
which may seem so unphilosophical, is intended only to express that act
of the mind, which renders realities, or what is taken for such, more present
to us than fictions, causes them to weigh more in the thought, and gives
them a superior influence on the passions and imagination. Provided we
agree about the thing, it is needless to dispute about the terms. The imagination
has the command over all its ideas, and can join and mix and vary them,
in all the ways possible. It may conceive fictitious objects with all the
circumstances of place and time. It may set them, in a manner, before our
eyes, in their true colours, just as they might have existed. But as it
is impossible that this faculty of imagination can ever, of itself, reach
belief, it is evident that belief consists not in the peculiar nature or
order of ideas, but in the manner of their conception, and in their feeling
to the mind. I confess, that it is impossible perfectly to explain this
feeling or manner of conception. We may make use of words which express
something near it. But its true and proper name, as we observed before,
is belief; which is a term that every one sufficiently understands in common
life. And in philosophy, we can go no farther than assert, that belief
is something felt by the mind, which distinguishes the ideas of the judgement
from the fictions of the imagination. It gives them more weight and influence;
makes them appear of greater importance; enforces them in the mind; and
renders them the governing principle of our actions. I hear at present,
for instance, a person's voice, with whom I am acquainted; and the sound
comes as from the next room. This impression of my senses immediately conveys
my thought to the person, together with all the surrounding objects. I
paint them out to myself as existing at present, with the same qualities
and relations, of which I formerly knew them possessed. These ideas take
faster hold of my mind than ideas of an enchanted castle. They are very
different to the feeling, and have a much greater influence of every kind,
either to give pleasure or pain, joy or sorrow.
Let us, then, take in the whole compass
of this doctrine, and allow, that the sentiment of belief is nothing but
a conception more intense and steady than what attends the mere fictions
of the imagination, and that this manner of conception arises from a customary
conjunction of the object with something present to the memory or senses:
I believe that it will not be difficult, upon these suppositions, to find
other operations of the mind analogous to it, and to trace up these phenomena
to principles still more general.
We have already observed that nature has
established connexions among particular ideas, and that no sooner one idea
occurs to our thoughts than it introduces its correlative, and carries
our attention towards it, by a gentle and insensible movement. These principles
of connexion or association we have reduced to three, namely, Resemblance,
Contiguity and Causation; which are the only bonds that unite our thoughts
together, and beget that regular train of reflection or discourse, which,
in a greater or less degree, takes place among all mankind. Now here arises
a question, on which the solution of the present difficulty will depend.
Does it happen, in all these relations, that, when one of the objects is
presented to the senses or memory, the mind is not only carried to the
conception of the correlative, but reaches a steadier and stronger conception
of it than what otherwise it would have been able to attain? This seems
to be the case with that belief which arises from the relation of cause
and effect. And if the case be the same with the other relations or principles
of associations, this may be established as a general law, which takes
place in all the operations of the mind.
We may, therefore, observe, as the first
experiment to our present purpose, that, upon the appearance of the picture
of an absent friend, our idea of him is evidently enlivened by the resemblance,
and that every passion, which that idea occasions, whether of joy or sorrow,
acquires new force and vigour. In producing this effect, there concur both
a relation and a present impression. Where the picture bears him no resemblance,
at least was not intended for him, it never so much as conveys our thought
to him: and where it is absent, as well as the person, though the mind
may pass from the thought of the one to that of the other, it feels its
idea to be rather weakened than enlivened by that transition. We take a
pleasure in viewing the picture of a friend, when it is set before us;
but when it is removed, rather choose to consider him directly than by
reflection in an image, which is equally distant and obscure.
The ceremonies of the Roman Catholic religion
may be considered as instances of the same nature. The devotees of that
superstition usually plead in excuse for the mummeries, with which they
are upbraided, that they feel the good effect of those external motions,
and postures, and actions, in enlivening their devotion and quickening
their fervour, which otherwise would decay, if directed entirely to distant
and immaterial objects. We shadow out the objects of our faith, say they,
in sensible types and images, and render them more present to us by the
immediate presence of these types, than it is possible for us to do merely
by an intellectual view and contemplation. Sensible objects have always
a greater influence on the fancy than any other; and this influence they
readily convey to those ideas to which they are related, and which they
resemble. I shall only infer from these practices, and this reasoning,
that the effect of resemblance in enlivening the ideas is very common;
and as in every case a resemblance and a present impression must concur,
we are abundantly supplied with experiments to prove the reality of the
foregoing principle.
We may add force to these experiments by
others of a different kind, in considering the effects of contiguity as
well as of resemblance. It is certain that distance diminishes the force
of every idea, and that, upon our approach to any object; though it does
not discover itself to our senses; it operates upon the mind with an influence,
which imitates an immediate impression. The thinking on any object readily
transports the mind to what is contiguous; but it is only the actual presence
of an object, that transports it with a superior vivacity. When I am a
few miles from home, whatever relates to it touches me more nearly than
when I am two hundred leagues distant; though even at that distance the
reflecting on any thing in the neighbourhood of my friends or family naturally
produces an idea of them. But as in this latter case, both the objects
of the mind are ideas; notwithstanding there is an easy transition between
them; that transition alone is not able to give a superior vivacity to
any of the ideas, for want of some immediate impression.[2]
No one can doubt but causation has the
same influence as the other two relations of resemblance and contiguity.
Superstitious people are fond of the reliques of saints and holy men, for
the same reason, that they seek after types or images, in order to enliven
their devotion, and give them a more intimate and strong conception of
those exemplary lives, which they desire to imitate. Now it is evident,
that one of the best reliques, which a devotee could procure, would be
the handywork of a saint; and if his cloaths and furniture are ever to
be considered in this light, it is because they were once at his disposal,
and were moved and affected by him; in which respect they are to be considered
as imperfect effects, and as connected with him by a shorter chain of consequences
than any of those, by which we learn the reality of his existence.
Suppose, that the son of a friend, who
had been long dead or absent, were presented to us; it is evident, that
this object would instantly revive its correlative idea, and recall to
our thoughts all past intimacies and familiarities, in more lively colours
than they would otherwise have appeared to us. This is another phaenomenon,
which seems to prove the principle above mentioned.
We may observe, that, in these phaenomena,
the belief of the correlative object is always presupposed; without which
the relation could have no effect. The influence of the picture supposes,
that we believe our friend to have once existed. Contiguity to home can
never excite our ideas of home, unless we believe that it really exists.
Now I assert, that this belief, where it reaches beyond the memory or senses,
is of a similar nature, and arises from similar causes, with the transition
of thought and vivacity of conception here explained. When I throw a piece
of dry wood into a fire, my mind is immediately carried to conceive, that
it augments, not extinguishes the flame. This transition of thought from
the cause to the effect proceeds not from reason. It derives its origin
altogether from custom and experience. And as it first begins from an object,
present to the senses, it renders the idea or conception of flame more
strong and lively than any loose, floating reverie of the imagination.
That idea arises immediately. The thought moves instantly towards it, and
conveys to it all that force of conception, which is derived from the impression
present to the senses. When a sword is levelled at my breast, does not
the idea of wound and pain strike me more strongly, than when a glass of
wine is presented to me, even though by accident this idea should occur
after the appearance of the latter object? But what is there in this whole
matter to cause such a strong conception, except only a present object
and a customary transition of the idea of another object, which we have
been accustomed to conjoin with the former? This is the whole operation
of the mind, in all our conclusions concerning matter of fact and existence;
and it is a satisfaction to find some analogies, by which it may be explained.
The transition from a present object does in all cases give strength and
solidity to the related idea.
Here, then, is a kind of pre-established
harmony between the course of nature and the succession of our ideas; and
though the powers and forces, by which the former is governed, be wholly
unknown to us; yet our thoughts and conceptions have still, we find, gone
on in the same train with the other works of nature. Custom is that principle,
by which this correspondence has been effected; so necessary to the subsistence
of our species, and the regulation of our conduct, in every circumstance
and occurrence of human life. Had not the presence of an object, instantly
excited the idea of those objects, commonly conjoined with it, all our
knowledge must have been limited to the narrow sphere of our memory and
senses; and we should never have been able to adjust means to ends, or
employ our natural powers, either to the producing of good, or avoiding
of evil. Those, who delight in the discovery and contemplation of final
causes, have here ample subject to employ their wonder and admiration.
I shall add, for a further confirmation
of the foregoing theory, that, as this operation of the mind, by which
we infer like effects from like causes, and vice versa, is so essential
to the subsistence of all human creatures, it is not probable, that it
could be trusted to the fallacious deductions of our reason, which is slow
in its operations; appears not, in any degree, during the first years of
infancy; and at best is, in every age and period of human life, extremely
liable to error and mistake. It is more conformable to the ordinary wisdom
of nature to secure so necessary an act of the mind, by some instinct or
mechanical tendency, which may be infallible in its operations, may discover
itself at the first appearance of life and thought, and may be independent
of all the laboured deductions of the understanding. As nature has taught
us the use of our limbs, without giving us the knowledge of the muscles
and nerves, by which they are actuated; so has she implanted in us an instinct,
which carries forward the thought in a correspondent course to that which
she has established among external objects; though we are ignorant of those
powers and forces, on which this regular course and succession of objects
totally depends.
[1] Nothing is more useful than for writers,
even, on moral, political, or physical subjects, to distinguish between
reason and experience, and to suppose, that these species of argumentation
are entirely different from each other. The former are taken for the mere
result of our intellectual faculties, which, by considering a priori the
nature of things, and examining the effects, that must follow from their
operation, establish particular principles of science and philosophy. The
latter are supposed to be derived entirely from sense and observation,
by which we learn what has actually resulted from the operation of particular
objects, and are thence able to infer, what will, for the future, result
from them. Thus, for instance, the limitations and restraints of civil
government, and a legal constitution, may be defended, either from reason,
which reflecting on the great frailty and corruption of human nature, teaches,
that no man can safely be trusted with unlimited authority; or from experience
and history, which inform us of the enormous abuses, that ambition, in
every age and country, has been found to make so imprudent a confidence.
The same distinction between reason and
experience is maintained in all our deliberations concerning the conduct
of life; while the experienced statesman, general, physician, or merchant
is trusted and followed; and the unpractised novice, with whatever natural
talents endowed, neglected and despised. Though it be allowed, that reason
may form very plausible conjectures with regard to the consequences of
such a particular conduct in such particular circumstances; it is still
supposed imperfect, without the assistance of experience, which is alone
able to give stability and certainty to the maxims, derived from study
and reflection.
But notwithstanding that this distinction
be thus universally received, both in the active and speculative scenes
of life, I shall not scruple to pronounce, that it is, at bottom, erroneous,
at least, superficial.
If we examine those arguments, which, in
any of the sciences above mentioned, are supposed to be mere effects of
reasoning and reflection, they will be found to terminate, at last, in
some general principle or, conclusion, for which we can assign no reason
but observation and experience. The only difference between them and those
maxims, which are vulgarly esteemed the result of pure experience, is,
that the former cannot be established without some process of thought,
and some reflection on what we have observed, in order to distinguish its
circumstances, and trace its consequences: Whereas in the latter, the experienced
event is exactly and fully familiar to that which we infer as the result
of any particular situation. The history of a TIBERIUS or a NERO makes
us dread a like tyranny, were our monarchs freed from the restraints of
laws and senates: But the observation of any fraud or cruelty in private
life is sufficient, with the aid of a little thought, to give us the same
apprehension; while it serves as an instance of the general corruption
of human nature, and shows us the danger which we must incur by reposing
an entire confidence in mankind. In both cases, it is experience which
is ultimately the foundation of our inference and conclusion.
There is no man so young and inexperienced,
as not to have formed, from observation, many general and just maxims concerning
human affairs and the conduct of life; but it must be confessed, that,
when a man comes to put these in practice, he will be extremely liable
to error, till time and farther experience both enlarge these maxims, and
teach him their proper use and application. In every situation or incident,
there are many particular and seemingly minute circumstances, which the
man of greatest talent is, at first, apt to overlook, though on them the
justness of his conclusions, and consequently the prudence of his conduct,
entirely depend. Not to mention, that, to a young beginner, the general
observations and maxims occur not always on the proper occasions, nor can
be immediately applied with due calmness and distinction. The truth is,
an unexperienced reasoner could be no reasoner at all, were he absolutely
unexperienced; and when we assign that character to any one, we mean it
only in a comparative sense, and suppose him possessed of experience, in
a smaller and more imperfect degree.
[2] 'Naturane nobis, inquit, datum dicam,
an errore quodam, ut, cum ea loca videamus, in quibus memoria dignos viros
acceperimus multim esse versatos, magis moveamur, quam siquando eorum ipsorum
aut facta audiamus aut scriptum aliquod legamus? Velut ego nunc moveor.
Venit enim mihi Plato in mentem, quem accepimus primum hic disputare solitum;
cuius etiam illi hortuli propinqui non memoriam solum mihi afferunt, sed
ipsum videntur in conspectu meo hic ponere. Hic Speusippus, hic Xenocrates,
hic eius auditor Polemo; cuius ipsa illa sessio fuit, quam videmus. Equidem
etiam curiam nostram, Hostiliam dico, non hanc novam, quae mihi minor esse
videtur postquam est maior, solebam intuens, Scipionem, Catonem, Laelium,
nostrum vero in primis avum cogitare. Tanta vis admonitionis est in locis;
ut non sine causa ex his memopriae deducta sit disciplina.'-Cicero de Finibus.
Lib. v.
SECTION VI: OF PROBABILITY[1]
THOUGH there be no such thing as Chance in
the world; our ignorance of the real cause of any event has the same influence
on the understanding, and begets a like species of belief or opinion.
There is certainly a probability, which
arises from a superiority of chances on any side; and according as this
superiority increases, and surpasses the opposite chances, the probability
receives a proportionable increase, and begets still a higher degree of
belief or assent to that side, in which we discover the superiority. If
a dye were marked with one figure or number of spots on four sides, and
with another figure or number of spots on the two remaining sides, it would
be more probable, that the former would turn up than the latter; though,
if it had a thousand sides marked in the same manner, and only one side
different, the probability would be much higher, and our belief or expectation
of the event more steady and secure. This process of the thought or reasoning
may seem trivial and obvious; but to those who consider it more narrowly,
it may, perhaps, afford matter for curious speculation.
It seems evident, that, when the mind looks
forward to discover the event, which may result from the throw of such
a dye, it considers the turning up of each particular side as alike probable;
and this is the very nature of chance, to render all the particular events,
comprehended in it, entirely equal. But finding a greater number of sides
concur in the one event than in the other, the mind is carried more frequently
to that event, and meets it oftener, in revolving the various possibilities
or chances, on which the ultimate result depends. This concurrence of several
views in one particular event begets immediately, by an inexplicable contrivance
of nature, the sentiment of belief, and gives that event the advantage
over its antagonist, which is supported by a smaller number of views, and
recurs less frequently to the mind. If we allow, that belief is nothing
but a firmer and stronger conception of an object than what attends the
mere fictions of the imagination, this operation may, perhaps, in some
measure, be accounted for. The concurrence of these several views or glimpses
imprints the idea more strongly on the imagination; gives it superior force
and vigour; renders its influence on the passions and affections more sensible;
and in a word, begets that reliance or security, which constitutes the
nature of belief and opinion.
The case is the same with the probability
of causes, as with that of chance. There are some causes, which are entirely
uniform and constant in producing a particular effect; and no instance
has ever yet been found of any failure or irregularity in their operation.
Fire has always burned, and water suffocated every human creature: the
production of motion by impulse and gravity is an universal law, which
has hitherto admitted of no exception. But there are other causes, which
have been found more irregular and uncertain; nor has rhubarb always proved
a purge, or opium a soporific to every one, who has taken these medicines.
It is true, when any cause fails of producing its usual effect, philosophers
ascribe not this to any irregularity in nature; but suppose, that some
secret causes, in the particular structure of parts, have prevented the
operation. Our reasonings, however, and conclusions concerning the event
are the same as if this principle had no place. Being determined by custom
to transfer the past to the future, in all our inferences; where the past
has been entirely regular and uniform, we expect the event with the greatest
assurance, and leave no room for any contrary supposition. But where different
effects have been found to follow from causes, which are to appearance
exactly similar, all these various effects must occur to the mind in transferring
the past to the future, and enter into our consideration, when we determine
the probability of the event. Though we give the preference to that which
has been found most usual, and believe that this effect will exist, we
must not overlook the other effects, but must assign to each of them a
particular weight and authority, in proportion as we have found it to be
more or less frequent. It is more probable, in almost every country of
Europe, that there will be frost sometime in January, than that the weather
will continue open through out that whole month; though this probability
varies according to the different climates, and approaches to a certainty
in the more northern kingdoms. Here then it seems evident, that, when we
transfer the past to the future, in order to determine the effect, which
will result from any cause, we transfer all the different events, in the
same proportion as they have appeared in the past, and conceive one to
have existed a hundred times, for instance, another ten times, and another
once. As a great number of views do here concur in one event, they fortify
and confirm it to the imagination, beget that sentiment which we call belief,
and give its object the preference above the contrary event, which is not
supported by an equal number of experiments, and recurs not so frequently
to the thought in transferring the past to the future. Let any one try
to account for this operation of the mind upon any of the received systems
of philosophy, and he will be sensible of the difficulty. For my part,
I shall think it sufficient, if the present hints excite the curiosity
of philosophers, and make them sensible how defective all common theories
are in treating of such curious and such sublime subjects.
[1] Mr. Locke divides all arguments into
demonstrative and probable. In this view, we must say, that it is only
probable that all men must die, or that the sun will rise to-morrow. But
to conform our language more to common use, we ought to divide arguments
into demonstrations, proofs, and probabilities. By proofs meaning such
arguments from experience as leave no room for doubt or opposition.
SECTION VII: OF THE
IDEA OF NECESSARY CONNEXION
PART I
THE great advantage of the mathematical sciences
above the moral consists in this, that the ideas of the former, being sensible,
are always clear and determinate, the smallest distinction between them
is immediately perceptible, and the same terms are still expressive of
the same ideas, without ambiguity or variation. An oval is never mistaken
for a circle, nor an hyperbola for an ellipsis. The isosceles and scalenum
are distinguished by boundaries more exact than vice and virtue, right
and wrong. If any term be defined in geometry, the mind readily, of itself,
substitutes, on all occasions, the definition for the term defined: or
even when no definition is employed, the object itself may be presented
to the senses, and by that means be steadily and clearly apprehended. But
the finer sentiments of the mind, the operations of the understanding,
the various agitations of the passions, though really in themselves distinct,
easily escape us, when surveyed by reflection; nor is it in our power to
recall the original object, as often as we have occasion to contemplate
it. Ambiguity, by this means, is gradually introduced into our reasonings:
similar objects are readily taken to be the same: and the conclusion becomes
at last very wide of the premises.
One may safely, however, affirm, that,
if we consider these sciences in a proper light, their advantages and disadvantages
nearly compensate each other, and reduce both of them to a state of equality.
If the mind, with greater facility, retains the ideas of geometry clear
and determinate, it must carry on a much longer and more intricate chain
of reasoning, and compare ideas much wider of each other, in order to reach
the abstruser truths of that science. And if moral ideas are apt, without
extreme care, to fall into obscurity and confusion, the inferences are
always much shorter in these disquisitions, and the intermediate steps,
which lead to the conclusion, much fewer than in the sciences which treat
of quantity and number. In reality, there is scarcely a proposition in
Euclid so simple, as not to consist of more parts, than are to be found
in any moral reasoning which runs not into chimera and conceit. Where we
trace the principles of the human mind through a few steps, we may be very
well satisfied with our progress; considering how soon nature throws a
bar to all our enquiries concerning causes, and reduces us to an acknowledgment
of our ignorance. The chief obstacle, therefore, to our improvement in
the moral or metaphysical sciences is the obscurity of the ideas, and ambiguity
of the terms. The principal difficulty in the mathematics is the length
of inferences and compass of thought, requisite to the forming of any conclusion.
And, perhaps, our progress in natural philosophy is chiefly retarded by
the want of proper experiments and phaenomena, which are often discovered
by chance, and cannot always be found, when requisite, even by the most
diligent and prudent enquiry. As moral philosophy seems hitherto to have
received less improvement than either geometry or physics, we may conclude,
that, if there be any difference in this respect among these sciences,
the difficulties, which obstruct the progress of the former, require superior
care and capacity to be surmounted.
There are no ideas, which occur in metaphysics,
more obscure and uncertain, than those of power, force, energy or necessary
connexion, of which it is every moment necessary for us to treat in all
our disquisitions. We shall, therefore, endeavour, in this section, to
fix, if possible, the precise meaning of these terms, and thereby remove
some part of that obscurity, which is so much complained of in this species
of philosophy.
It seems a proposition, which will not
admit of much dispute, that all our ideas are nothing but copies of our
impressions, or, in other words, that it is impossible for us to think
of anything, which we have not antecedently felt, either by our external
or internal senses. I have endeavoured[1] to explain and prove this proposition,
and have expressed my hopes, that, by a proper application of it, men may
reach a greater clearness and precision in philosophical reasonings, than
what they have hitherto been able to attain. Complex ideas, may, perhaps,
be well known by definition, which is nothing but an enumeration of those
parts or simple ideas, that compose them. But when we have pushed up definitions
to the most simple ideas, and find still more ambiguity and obscurity;
what resource are we then possessed of? By what invention can we throw
light upon these ideas, and render them altogether precise and determinate
to our intellectual view? Produce the impressions or original sentiments,
from which the ideas are copied. These impressions are all strong and sensible.
They admit not of ambiguity. They are not only placed in a full light themselves,
but may throw light on their correspondent ideas, which lie in obscurity.
And by this means, we may, perhaps, attain a new microscope or species
of optics, by which, in the moral sciences, the most minute, and most simple
ideas may be so enlarged as to fall readily under our apprehension, and
be equally known with the grossest and most sensible ideas, that can be
the object of our enquiry.
To be fully acquainted, therefore, with
the idea of power or necessary connexion, let us examine its impression;
and in order to find the impression with greater certainty, let us search
for it in all the sources, from which it may possibly be derived.
When we look about us towards external
objects, and consider the operation of causes, we are never able, in a
single instance, to discover any power or necessary connexion; any quality,
which binds the effect to the cause, and renders the one an infallible
consequence of the other. We only find, that the one does actually, in
fact, follow the other. The impulse of one billiard-ball is attended with
motion in the second. This is the whole that appears to the outward senses.
The mind feels no sentiment or inward impression from this succession of
objects: consequently, there is not, in any single, particular instance
of cause and effect, any thing which can suggest the idea of power or necessary
connexion.
From the first appearance of an object,
we never can conjecture what effect will result from it. But were the power
or energy of any cause discoverable by the mind, we could foresee the effect,
even without experience; and might, at first, pronounce with certainty
concerning it, by mere dint of thought and reasoning.
In reality, there is no part of matter,
that does ever, by its sensible qualities, discover any power or energy,
or give us ground to imagine, that it could produce any thing, or be followed
by any other object, which we could denominate its effect. Solidity, extension,
motion; these qualities are all complete in themselves, and never point
out any other event which may result from them. The scenes of the universe
are continually shifting, and one object follows another in an uninterrupted
succession; but the power of force, which actuates the whole machine, is
entirely concealed from us, and never discovers itself in any of the sensible
qualities of body. We know that, in fact, heat is a constant attendant
of flame; but what is the connexion between them, we have no room so much
as to conjecture or imagine. It is impossible, therefore, that the idea
of power can be derived from the contemplation of bodies, in single instances
of their operation; because no bodies ever discover any power, which can
be the original of this idea.[2]
Since, therefore, external objects as they
appear to the senses, give us no idea of power or necessary connexion,
by their operation in particular instances, let us see, whether this idea
be derived from reflection on the operations of our own minds, and be copied
from any internal impression. It may be said, that we are every moment
conscious of internal power; while we feel, that, by the simple command
of our will, we can move the organs of our body, or direct the faculties
of our mind. An act of volition produces motion in our limbs, or raises
a new idea in our imagination. This influence of the will we know by consciousness.
Hence we acquire the idea of power or energy; and are certain, that we
ourselves and all other intelligent beings are possessed of power. This
idea, then, is an idea of reflection, since it arises from reflecting on
the operations of our own mind, and on the command which is exercised by
will, both over the organs of the body and faculties of the soul.
We shall proceed to examine this pretension;
and first with regard to the influence of volition over the organs of the
body. This influence, we may observe, is a fact, which, like all other
natural events, can be known only by experience, and can never be foreseen
from any apparent energy or power in the cause, which connects it with
the effect, and renders the one an infallible consequence of the other.
The motion of our body follows upon the command of our will. Of this we
are every moment conscious. But the means, by which this is effected; the
energy, by which the will performs so extraordinary an operation; of this
we are so far from being immediately conscious, that it must for ever escape
our most diligent enquiry.
For first: Is there any principle in all
nature more mysterious than the union of soul with body; by which a supposed
spiritual substance acquires such an influence over a material one, that
the most refined thought is able to actuate the grossest matter? Were we
empowered, by a secret wish, to remove mountains, or control the planets
in their orbit; this extensive authority would not be more extraordinary,
nor more beyond our comprehension. But if by consciousness we perceived
any power or energy in the will, we must know this power; we must know
its connexion with the effect; we must know the secret union of soul and
body, and the nature of both these substances; by which the one is able
to operate, in so many instances, upon the other.
Secondly, We are not able to move all the
organs of the body with a like authority; though we cannot assign any reason
besides experience, for so remarkable a difference between one and the
other. Why has the will an influence over the tongue and fingers, not over
the heart or liver? This question would never embarrass us, were we conscious
of a power in the former case, not in the latter. We should then perceive,
independent of experience, why the authority of will over the organs of
the body is circumscribed within such particular limits. Being in that
case fully acquainted with the power or force, by which it operates, we
should also know, why its influence reaches precisely to such boundaries,
and no farther.
A man, suddenly struck with palsy in the
leg or arm, or who had newly lost those members, frequently endeavours,
at first to move them, and employ them, in their usual offices. Here he
is as much conscious of power to command such limbs, as a man in perfect
health is conscious of power to actuate any member which remains in its
natural state and condition. But consciousness never deceives. Consequently,
neither in the one case nor in the other, are we ever conscious of any
power. We learn the influence of our will from experience alone. And experience
only teaches us, how one event constantly follows another; without instructing
us in the secret connexion, which binds them together, and renders them
inseparable.
Thirdly, We learn from anatomy, that the
immediate object of power in voluntary motion, is not the member itself
which is moved, but certain muscles, and nerves, and animal spirits, and,
perhaps, something still more minute and more unknown, through which the
motion is successively propagated, ere it reach the member itself whose
motion is the immediate object of volition. Can there be a more certain
proof, that the power, by which this whole operation is performed, so far
from being directly and fully known by an inward sentiment or consciousness
is, to the last degree, mysterious and unintelligible? Here the mind wills
a certain event. Immediately another event, unknown to ourselves, and totally
different from the one intended, is produced: This event produces another,
equally unknown: till at last, through a long succession, the desired event
is produced. But if the original power were felt, it must be known: were
it known, its effect also must be known; since all power is relative to
its effect. And vice versa, if the effect be not known, the power cannot
be known nor felt. How indeed can we be conscious of a power to move our
limbs, when we have no such power; but only that to move certain animal
spirits, which, though they produce at last the motion of our limbs, yet
operate in such a manner as is wholly beyond our comprehension?
We may, therefore, conclude from the whole,
I hope, without any temerity, though with assurance; that our idea of power
is not copied from any sentiment or consciousness of power within ourselves,
when we give rise to animal motion, or apply our limbs to their proper
use and office. That their motion follows the command of the will is a
matter of common experience, like other natural events: But the power or
energy by which this is effected, like that in other natural events, is
unknown and inconceivable.[3]
Shall we then assert, that we are conscious
of a power or energy in our own minds, when, by an act or command of our
will, we raise up a new idea, fix the mind to the contemplation of it,
turn it on all sides, and at last dismiss it for some other idea, when
we think that we have surveyed it with sufficient accuracy? I believe the
same arguments will prove, that even this command of the will gives us
no real idea of force or energy.
First, It must be allowed, that, when we
know a power, we know that very circumstance in the cause, by which it
is enabled to produce the effect: for these are supposed to be synonymous.
We must, therefore, know both the cause and effect, and the relation between
them. But do we pretend to be acquainted with the nature of the human soul
and the nature of an idea, or the aptitude of the one to produce the other?
This is a real creation; a production of something out of nothing: which
implies a power so great, that it may seem, at first sight, beyond the
reach of any being, less than infinite. At least it must be owned, that
such a power is not felt, nor known, nor even conceivable by the mind.
We only feel the event, namely, the existence of an idea, consequent to
a command of the will: but the manner, in which this operation is performed,
the power by which it is produced, is entirely beyond our comprehension.
Secondly, The command of the mind over
itself is limited, as well as its command over the body; and these limits
are not known by reason, or any acquaintance with the nature of cause and
effect, but only by experience and observation, as in all other natural
events and in the operation of external objects. Our authority over our
sentiments and passions is much weaker than that over our ideas; and even
the latter authority is circumscribed within very narrow boundaries. Will
any one pretend to assign the ultimate reason of these boundaries, or show
why the power is deficient in one case, not in another.
Thirdly, This self-command is very different
at different times. A man in health possesses more of it than one languishing
with sickness. We are more master of our thoughts in the morning than in
the evening: fasting, than after a full meal. Can we give any reason for
these variations, except experience? Where then is the power, of which
we pretend to be conscious? Is there not here, either in a spiritual or
material substance, or both, some secret mechanism or structure of parts,
upon which the effect depends, and which, being entirely unknown to us,
renders the power or energy of the will equally unknown and incomprehensible?
Volition is surely an act of the mind,
with which we are sufficiently acquainted. Reflect upon it. Consider it
on all sides. Do you find anything in it like this creative power, by which
it raises from nothing a new idea, and with a kind of Fiat, imitates the
omnipotence of its Maker, if I may be allowed so to speak, who called forth
into existence all the various scenes of nature? So far from being conscious
of this energy in the will, it requires as certain experience as that of
which we are possessed, to convince us that such extraordinary effects
do ever result from a simple act of volition.
The generality of mankind never find any
difficulty in accounting for the more common and familiar operations of
nature--such as the descent of heavy bodies, the growth of plants, the
generation of animals, or the nourishment of bodies by food: but suppose
that, in all these cases, they perceive the very force or energy of the
cause, by which it is connected with its effect, and is for ever infallible
in its operation. They acquire, by long habit, such a turn of mind, that,
upon the appearance of the cause, they immediately expect with assurance
its usual attendant, and hardly conceive it possible that any other event
could result from it. It is only on the discovery of extraordinary phaenomena,
such as earthquakes, pestilence, and prodigies of any kind, that they find
themselves at a loss to assign a proper cause, and to explain the manner
in which the effect is produced by it. It is usual for men, in such difficulties,
to have recourse to some invisible intelligent principle[4] as the immediate
cause of that event which surprises them, and which, they think, cannot
be accounted for from the common powers of nature. But philosophers, who
carry their scrutiny a little farther, immediately perceive that, even
in the most familiar events, the energy of the cause is as unintelligible
as in the most unusual, and that we only learn by experience the frequent
Conjunction of objects, without being ever able to comprehend anything
like Connexion between them.
Here, then, many philosophers think themselves
obliged by reason to have recourse, on all occasions, to the same principle,
which the vulgar never appeal to but in cases that appear miraculous and
supernatural. They acknowledge mind and intelligence to be, not only the
ultimate and original cause of all things, but the immediate and sole cause
of every event which appears in nature. They pretend that those objects
which are commonly denominated causes, are in reality nothing but occasions;
and that the true and direct principle of every effect is not any power
or force in nature, but a volition of the Supreme Being, who wills that
such particular objects should for ever be conjoined with each other. Instead
of saying that one billiard-ball moves another by a force which it has
derived from the author of nature, it is the Deity himself, they say, who,
by a particular volition, moves the second ball, being determined to this
operation by the impulse of the first ball, in consequence of those general
laws which he has laid down to himself in the government of the universe.
But philosophers advancing still in their inquiries, discover that, as
we are totally ignorant of the power on which depends the mutual operation
of bodies, we are no less ignorant of that power on which depends the operation
of mind on body, or of body on mind, nor are we able, either from our senses
or consciousness, to assign the ultimate principle in one case more than
in the other. The same ignorance, therefore, reduces them to the same conclusion.
They assert that the Deity is the immediate cause of the union between
soul and body; and that they are not the organs of sense, which, being
agitated by external objects, produce sensations in the mind; but that
it is a particular volition of our omnipotent Maker, which excites such
a sensation, in consequence of such a motion in the organ. In like manner,
it is not any energy in the will that produces local motion in our members:
it is God himself, who is pleased to second our will, in itself impotent,
and to command that motion which we erroneously attribute to our own power
and efficacy. Nor do philosophers stop at this conclusion. They sometimes
extend the same inference to the mind itself, in its internal operations.
Our mental vision or conception of ideas is nothing but a revelation made
to us by our Maker. When we voluntarily turn our thoughts to any object,
and raise up its image in the fancy, it is not the will which creates that
idea: it is the universal Creator, who discovers it to the mind, and renders
it present to us.
Thus, according to these philosophers,
every thing is full of God. Not content with the principle, that nothing
exists but by his will, that nothing possesses any power but by his concession:
they rob nature, and all created beings, of every power, in order to render
their dependence on the Deity still more sensible and immediate. They consider
not that, by this theory, they diminish, instead of magnifying, the grandeur
of those attributes, which they affect so much to celebrate. It argues
surely more power in the Deity to delegate a certain degree of power to
inferior creatures than to produce every thing by his own immediate volition.
It argues more wisdom to contrive at first the fabric of the world with
such perfect foresight that, of itself, and by its proper operation, it
may serve all the purposes of providence, than if the great Creator were
obliged every moment to adjust its parts, and animate by his breath all
the wheels of that stupendous machine.
But if we would have a more philosophical
confutation of this theory, perhaps the two following reflections may suffice:
First, it seems to me that this theory
of the universal energy and operation of the Supreme Being is too bold
ever to carry conviction with it to a man, sufficiently apprized of the
weakness of human reason, and the narrow limits to which it is confined
in all its operations. Though the chain of arguments which conduct to it
were ever so logical, there must arise a strong suspicion, if not an absolute
assurance, that it has carried us quite beyond the reach of our faculties,
when it leads to conclusions so extraordinary, and so remote from common
life and experience. We are got into fairy land, long ere we have reached
the last steps of our theory; and there we have no reason to trust our
common methods of argument, or to think that our usual analogies and probabilities
have any authority. Our line is too short to fathom such immense abysses.
And however we may flatter ourselves that we are guided, in every step
which we take, by a kind of verisimilitude and experience, we may be assured
that this fancied experience has no authority when we thus apply it to
subjects that lie entirely out of the sphere of experience. But on this
we shall have occasion to touch afterwards.[5]
Secondly, I cannot perceive any force in
the arguments on which this theory is founded. We are ignorant, it is true,
of the manner in which bodies operate on each other: their force or energy
is entirely incomprehensible: but are we not equally ignorant of the manner
or force by which a mind, even the supreme mind, operates either on itself
or on body? Whence, I beseech you, do we acquire any idea of it? We have
no sentiment or consciousness of this power in ourselves. We have no idea
of the Supreme Being but what we learn from reflection on our own faculties.
Were our ignorance, therefore, a good reason for rejecting any thing, we
should be led into that principle of denying all energy in the Supreme
Being as much as in the grossest matter. We surely comprehend as little
the operations of one as of the other. Is it more difficult to conceive
that motion may arise from impulse than that it may arise from volition?
All we know is our profound ignorance in both cases.[6]
PART II
BUT to hasten to a conclusion of this argument,
which is already drawn out to too great a length: we have sought in vain
for an idea of power or necessary connexion in all the sources from which
we could suppose it to be derived. It appears that, in single instances
of the operation of bodies, we never can, by our utmost scrutiny, discover
any thing but one event following another, without being able to comprehend
any force or power by which the cause operates, or any connexion between
it and its supposed effect. The same difficulty occurs in contemplating
the operations of mind on body--where we observe the motion of the latter
to follow upon the volition of the former, but are not able to observe
or conceive the tie which binds together the motion and volition, or the
energy by which the mind produces this effect. The authority of the will
over its own faculties and ideas is not a whit more comprehensible: so
that, upon the whole, there appears not, throughout all nature, any one
instance of connexion which is conceivable by us. All events seem entirely
loose and separate. One event follows another; but we never can observe
any tie between them. They seem conjoined, but never connected. And as
we can have no idea of any thing which never appeared to our outward sense
or inward sentiment, the necessary conclusion seems to be that we have
no idea of connexion or power at all, and that these words are absolutely,
without any meaning, when employed either in philosophical reasonings or
common life.
But there still remains one method of avoiding
this conclusion, and one source which we have not yet examined. When any
natural object or event is presented, it is impossible for us, by any sagacity
or penetration, to discover, or even conjecture, without experience, what
event will result from it, or to carry our foresight beyond that object
which is immediately present to the memory and senses. Even after one instance
or experiment where we have observed a particular event to follow upon
another, we are not entitled to form a general rule, or foretell what will
happen in like cases; it being justly esteemed an unpardonable temerity
to judge of the whole course of nature from one single experiment, however
accurate or certain. But when one particular species of event has always,
in all instances, been conjoined with another, we make no longer any scruple
of foretelling one upon the appearance of the other, and of employing that
reasoning, which can alone assure us of any matter of fact or existence.
We then call the one object, Cause; the other, Effect. We suppose that
there is some connexion between them; some power in the one, by which it
infallibly produces the other, and operates with the greatest certainty
and strongest necessity.
It appears, then, that this idea of a necessary
connexion among events arises from a number of similar instances which
occur of the constant conjunction of these events; nor can that idea ever
be suggested by any one of these instances, surveyed in all possible lights
and positions. But there is nothing in a number of instances, different
from every single instance, which is supposed to be exactly similar; except
only, that after a repetition of similar instances, the mind is carried
by habit, upon the appearance of one event, to expect its usual attendant,
and to believe that it will exist. This connexion, therefore, which we
feel in the mind, this customary transition of the imagination from one
object to its usual attendant, is the sentiment or impression from which
we form the idea of power or necessary connexion. Nothing farther is in
the case. Contemplate the subject on all sides; you will never find any
other origin of that idea. This is the sole difference between one instance,
from which we can never receive the idea of connexion, and a number of
similar instances, by which it is suggested. The first time a man saw the
communication of motion by impulse, as by the shock of two billiard balls,
he could not pronounce that the one event was connected: but only that
it was conjoined with the other. After he has observed several instances
of this nature, he then pronounces them to be connected. What alteration
has happened to give rise to this new idea of connexion? Nothing but that
he now feels these events to be connected in his imagination, and can readily
foretell the existence of one from the appearance of the other. When we
say, therefore, that one object is connected with another, we mean only
that they have acquired a connexion in our thought, and give rise to this
inference, by which they become proofs of each other's existence: A conclusion
which is somewhat extraordinary, but which seems founded on sufficient
evidence. Nor will its evidence be weakened by any general diffidence of
the understanding, or sceptical suspicion concerning every conclusion which
is new and extraordinary. No conclusions can be more agreeable to scepticism
than such as make discoveries concerning the weakness and narrow limits
of human reason and capacity.
And what stronger instance can be produced
of the surprising ignorance and weakness of the understanding than the
present. For surely, if there be any relation among objects which it imports
to us to know perfectly, it is that of cause and effect. On this are founded
all our reasonings concerning matter of fact or existence. By means of
it alone we attain any assurance concerning objects which are removed from
the present testimony of our memory and senses. The only immediate utility
of all sciences, is to teach us, how to control and regulate future events
by their causes. Our thoughts and enquiries are, therefore, every moment,
employed about this relation: yet so imperfect are the ideas which we form
concerning it, that it is impossible to give any just definition of cause,
except what is drawn from something extraneous and foreign to it. Similar
objects are always conjoined with similar. Of this we have experience.
Suitably to this experience, therefore, we may define a cause to be an
object, followed by another, and where all the objects similar to the first
are followed by objects similar to the second. Or in other words where,
if the first object had not been, the second never had existed. The appearance
of a cause always conveys the mind, by a customary transition, to the idea
of the effect. Of this also we have experience. We may, therefore, suitably
to this experience, form another definition of cause, and call it, an object
followed by another, and whose appearance always conveys the thought to
that other. But though both these definitions be drawn from circumstances
foreign to the cause, we cannot remedy this inconvenience, or attain any
more perfect definition, which may point out that circumstance in the cause,
which gives it a connexion with its effect. We have no idea of this connexion,
nor even any distant notion what it is we desire to know, when we endeavour
at a conception of it. We say, for instance, that the vibration of this
string is the cause of this particular sound. But what do we mean by that
affirmation? We either mean that this vibration is followed by this sound,
and that all similar vibrations have been followed by similar sounds; or,
that this vibration is followed by this sound, and that upon the appearance
of one the mind anticipates the senses, and forms immediately an idea of
the other. We may consider the relation of cause and effect in either of
these two lights; but beyond these, we have no idea of it.[7]
To recapitulate, therefore, the reasonings
of this section: Every idea is copied from some preceding impression or
sentiment; and where we cannot find any impression, we may be certain that
there is no idea. In all single instances of the operation of bodies or
minds, there is nothing that produces any impression, nor consequently
can suggest any idea of power or necessary connexion. But when many uniform
instances appear, and the same object is always followed by the same event;
we then begin to entertain the notion of cause and connexion. We then feel
a new sentiment or impression, to wit, a customary connexion in the thought
or imagination between one object and its usual attendant; and this sentiment
is the original of that idea which we seek for. For as this idea arises
from a number of similar instances, and not from any single instance, it
must arise from that circumstance, in which the number of instances differ
from every individual instance. But this customary connexion or transition
of the imagination is the only circumstance in which they differ. In every
other particular they are alike. The first instance which we saw of motion
communicated by the shock of two billiard balls (to return to this obvious
illustration) is exactly similar to any instance that may, at present,
occur to us; except only, that we could not, at first, infer one event
from the other; which we are enabled to do at present, after so long a
course of uniform experience. I know not whether the reader will readily
apprehend this reasoning. I am afraid that, should I multiply words about
it, or throw it into a greater variety of lights, it would only become
more obscure and intricate. In all abstract reasonings there is one point
of view which, if we can happily hit, we shall go farther towards illustrating
the subject than by all the eloquence and copious expression in the world.
This point of view we should endeavour to reach, and reserve the flowers
of rhetoric for subjects which are more adapted to them.
[1] Section II.
[2] Mr. Locke, in his chapter of power,
says that, finding from experience, that there are several new productions
in matter, and concluding that there must somewhere be a power capable
of producing them, we arrive at last by this reasoning at the idea of power.
But no reasoning can ever give us a new, original, simple idea; as this
philosopher himself confesses. This, therefore, can never be the origin
of that idea.
[3] It may be pretended, that the resistance
which we meet with in bodies, obliging us frequently to exert our force,
and call up all our power, this gives us the idea of force and power. It
is this nisus, or strong endeavour, of which we are conscious, that is
the original impression from which this idea is copied. But, first, we
attribute power to a vast number of objects, where we never can suppose
this resistance or exertion of force to take place; to the Supreme Being,
who never meets with any resistance; to the mind in its command over its
ideas and limbs, in common thinking and motion, where the effect follows
immediately upon the will, without any exertion or summoning up of force;
to inanimate matter, which is not capable of this sentiment. Secondly,
This sentiment of an endeavour to overcome resistance has no known connexion
with any event: What follows it, we know by experience; but could not know
it a priori. It must, however, be confessed, that the animal nisus, which
we experience, though it can afford no accurate precise idea of power,
enters very much into that vulgar, inaccurate idea, which is formed by
it.
[4] [three greek words]
[5] Section XII.
[6] I need not examine at length the vis
inertiae which is so much talked of in the new philosophy, and which is
ascribed to matter. We find by experience, that a body at rest or in motion
continues for ever in its present state, till put from it by some new cause;
and that a body impelled takes as much motion from the impelling body as
it acquires itself. These are facts. When we call this a vis inertiae,
we only mark these facts, without pretending to have any idea of the inert
power; in the same manner as, when we talk of gravity, we mean certain
effects, without comprehending that active power. It was never the meaning
of Sir ISAAC NEWTON to rob second causes of all force or energy; though
some of his followers have endeavoured to establish that theory upon his
authority. On the contrary, that great philosopher had recourse to an etherial
active fluid to explain his universal attraction; though he was so cautious
and modest as to allow, that it was a mere hypothesis, no to be insisted
on, without more experiments. I must confess, that there is something in
the fate of opinions a little extraordinary. DES CARTES insinuated that
doctrine of the universal and sole efficacy of the Deity, without insisting
on it. MALEBRANCHE and other CARTESIANS made it the foundation of all their
philosophy. It had, however, no authority in England. LOCKE, CLARKE, and
CUDWORTH, never so much as notice of it, but suppose all along, that matter
has a real, though subordinate and derived power. By what means has it
become so prevalent among our modern metaphysicians?
[7] According to these explications and
definitions, the idea of power is relative as much as that of cause; and
both have a reference to an effect, or some other event constantly conjoined
with the former. When we consider the unknown circumstance of an object,
by which the degree or quantity of its effect is fixed and determined,
we call that its power: and accordingly, it is allowed by all philosophers,
that the effect is the measure of the power. But if they had any idea of
power, as it is in itself, why could not they Measure it in itself? The
dispute whether the force of a body in motion be as its velocity, or the
square of its velocity; this dispute, I say, need not be decided by comparing
its effects in equal or unequal times; but by a direct mensuration and
comparison.
As to the frequent use of the words, Force,
Power, Energy, &c., which every where occur in common conversation,
as well as in philosophy; that is no proof, that we are acquainted, in
any instance, with the connecting principle between cause and effect, or
can account ultimately for the production of one thing to another. These
words, as commonly used, have very loose meanings annexed to them; and
their ideas are very uncertain and confused. No animal can put external
bodies in motion without the sentiment of a nisus or endeavour; and every
animal has a sentiment or feeling from the stroke or blow of an external
object, that is in motion. These sensations, which are merely animal, and
from which we can a priori draw no inference, we are apt to transfer to
inanimate objects, and to suppose, that they have some such feelings, whenever
they transfer or receive motion. With regard to energies, which are exerted,
without our annexing to them any idea of communicated motion, we consider
only the constant experienced conjunction of the events; and as we feel
a customary connexion between the ideas, we transfer that feeling to the
objects; as nothing is more usual than to apply to external bodies every
internal sensation, which they occasion.
SECTION VIII: OF LIBERTY
AND NECESSITY
PART I
IT might reasonably be expected in questions
which have been canvassed and disputed with great eagerness, since the
first origin of science, and philosophy, that the meaning of all the terms,
at least, should have been agreed upon among the disputants; and our enquiries,
in the course of two thousand years, been able to pass from words to the
true and real subject of the controversy. For how easy may it seem to give
exact definitions of the terms employed in reasoning, and make these definitions,
not the mere sound of words, the object of future scrutiny and examination?
But if we consider the matter more narrowly, we shall be apt to draw a
quite opposite conclusion. From this circumstance alone, that a controversy
has been long kept on foot, and remains still undecided, we may presume
that there is some ambiguity in the expression, and that the disputants
affix different ideas to the terms employed in the controversy. For as
the faculties of the mind are supposed to be naturally alike in every individual;
otherwise nothing could be more fruitless than to reason or dispute together;
it were impossible, if men affix the same ideas to their terms, that they
could so long form different opinions of the same subject; especially when
they communicate their views, and each party turn themselves on all sides,
in search of arguments which may give them the victory over their antagonists.
It is true, if men attempt the discussion of questions which lie entirely
beyond the reach of human capacity, such as those concerning the origin
of worlds, or the economy of the intellectual system or region of spirits,
they may long beat the air in their fruitless contests, and never arrive
at any determinate conclusion. But if the question regard any subject of
common life and experience, nothing, one would think, could preserve the
dispute so long undecided but some ambiguous expressions, which keep the
antagonists still at a distance, and hinder them from grappling with each
other.
This has been the case in the long disputed
question concerning liberty and necessity; and to so remarkable a degree
that, if I be not much mistaken, we shall find, that all mankind, both
learned and ignorant, have always been of the same opinion with regard
to this subject, and that a few intelligible definitions would immediately
have put an end to the whole controversy. I own that this dispute has been
so much canvassed on all hands, and has led philosophers into such a labyrinth
of obscure sophistry, that it is no wonder, if a sensible reader indulge
his ease so far as to turn a deaf ear to the proposal of such a question,
from which he can expect neither instruction or entertainment. But the
state of the argument here proposed may, perhaps, serve to renew his attention;
as it has more novelty, promises at least some decision of the controversy,
and will not much disturb his ease by any intricate or obscure reasoning.
I hope, therefore, to make it appear that
all men have ever agreed in the doctrine both of necessity and of liberty,
according to any reasonable sense, which can be put on these terms; and
that the whole controversy, has hitherto turned merely upon words. We shall
begin with examining the doctrine of necessity.
It is universally allowed that matter,
in all its operations, is actuated by a necessary force, and that every
natural effect is so precisely determined by the energy of its cause that
no other effect, in such particular circumstances, could possibly have
resulted from it. The degree and direction of every motion is, by the laws
of nature, prescribed with such exactness that a living creature may as
soon arise from the shock of two bodies as motion in any other degree or
direction than what is actually produced by it. Would we, therefore, form
a just and precise idea of necessity, we must consider whence that idea
arises when we apply it to the operation of bodies.
It seems evident that, if all the scenes
of nature were continually shifted in such a manner that no two events
bore any resemblance to each other, but every object was entirely new,
without any similitude to whatever had been seen before, we should never,
in that case, have attained the least idea of necessity, or of a connexion
among these objects. We might say, upon such a supposition, that one object
or event has followed another; not that one was produced by the other.
The relation of cause and effect must be utterly unknown to mankind. Inference
and reasoning concerning the operations of nature would, from that moment,
be at an end; and the memory and senses remain the only canals, by which
the knowledge of any real existence could possibly have access to the mind.
Our idea, therefore, of necessity and causation arises entirely from the
uniformity observable in the operations of nature, where similar objects
are constantly conjoined together, and the mind is determined by custom
to infer the one from the appearance of the other. These two circumstances
form the whole of that necessity, which we ascribe to matter. Beyond the
constant conjunction of similar objects, and the consequent inference from
one to the other, we have no notion of any necessity or connexion.
If it appear, therefore, that all mankind
have ever allowed, without any doubt or hesitation, that these two circumstances
take place in the voluntary actions of men, and in the operations of mind;
it must follow, that all mankind have ever agreed in the doctrine of necessity,
and that they have hitherto disputed, merely for not understanding each
other.
As to the first circumstance, the constant
and regular conjunction of similar events, we may possibly satisfy ourselves
by the following considerations: It is universally acknowledged that there
is a great uniformity among the actions of men, in all nations and ages,
and that human nature remains still the same, in its principles and operations.
The same motives always produce the same actions: the same events follow
from the same causes. Ambition, avarice, self-love, vanity, friendship,
generosity, public spirit: these passions, mixed in various degrees, and
distributed through society, have been, from the beginning of the world,
and still are, the source of all the actions and enterprises, which have
ever been observed among mankind. Would you know the sentiments, inclinations,
and course of life of the Greeks and Romans? Study well the temper and
actions of the French and English: You cannot be much mistaken in transferring
to the former most of the observations which you have made with regard
to the latter. Mankind are so much the same, in all times and places, that
history informs us of nothing new or strange in this particular. Its chief
use is only to discover the constant and universal principles of human
nature, by showing men in all varieties of circumstances and situations,
and furnishing us with materials from which we may form our observations
and become acquainted with the regular springs of human action and behaviour.
These records of wars, intrigues, factions, and revolutions, are so many
collections of experiments, by which the politician or moral philosopher
fixes the principles of his science, in the same manner as the physician
or natural philosopher becomes acquainted with the nature of plants, minerals,
and other external objects, by the experiments which he forms concerning
them. Nor are the earth, water, and other elements, examined by Aristotle,
and Hippocrates, more like to those which at present lie under our observation
than the men described by Polybius and Tacitus are to those who now govern
the world.
Should a traveller, returning from a far
country, bring us an account of men, wholly different from any with whom
we were ever acquainted; men, who were entirely divested of avarice, ambition,
or revenge; who knew no pleasure but friendship, generosity, and public
spirit; we should immediately, from these circumstances, detect the falsehood,
and prove him a liar, with the same certainty as if he had stuffed his
narration with stories of centaurs and dragons, miracles and prodigies.
And if we would explode any forgery in history, we cannot make use of a
more convincing argument, than to prove, that the actions ascribed to any
person are directly contrary to the course of nature, and that no human
motives, in such circumstances, could ever induce him to such a conduct.
The veracity of Quintus Curtius is as much to be suspected, when he describes
the supernatural courage of Alexander, by which he was hurried on singly
to attack multitudes, as when he describes his supernatural force and activity,
by which he was able to resist them. So readily and universally do we acknowledge
a uniformity in human motives and actions as well as in the operations
of body.
Hence likewise the benefit of that experience,
acquired by long life and a variety of business and company, in order to
instruct us in the principles of human nature, and regulate our future
conduct, as well as speculation. By means of this guide, we mount up to
the knowledge of men's inclinations and motives, from their actions, expressions,
and even gestures; and again descend to the interpretation of their actions
from our knowledge of their motives and inclinations. The general observations
treasured up by a course of experience, give us the clue of human nature,
and teach us to unravel all its intricacies. Pretexts and appearances no
longer deceive us. Public declarations pass for the specious colouring
of a cause. And though virtue and honour be allowed their proper weight
and authority, that perfect disinterestedness, so often pretended to, is
never expected in multitudes and parties; seldom in their leaders; and
scarcely even in individuals of any rank or station. But were there no
uniformity in human actions, and were every experiment which we could form
of this kind irregular and anomalous, it were impossible to collect any
general observations concerning mankind; and no experience, however accurately
digested by reflection, would ever serve to any purpose. Why is the aged
husbandman more skilful in his calling than the young beginner but because
there is a certain uniformity in the operation of the sun, rain, and earth
towards the production of vegetables; and experience teaches the old practitioner
the rules by which this operation is governed and directed.
We must not, however, expect that this
uniformity of human actions should be carried to such a length as that
all men, in the same circumstances, will always act precisely in the same
manner, without making any allowance for the diversity of characters, prejudices,
and opinions. Such a uniformity in every particular, is found in no part
of nature. On the contrary, from observing the variety of conduct in different
men, we are enabled to form a greater variety of maxims, which still suppose
a degree of uniformity and regularity.
Are the manners of men different in different
ages and countries? We learn thence the great force of custom and education,
which mould the human mind from its infancy and form it into a fixed and
established character. Is the behaviour and conduct of the one sex very
unlike that of the other? Is it thence we become acquainted with the different
characters which nature has impressed upon the sexes, and which she preserves
with constancy and regularity? Are the actions of the same person much
diversified in the different periods of his life, from infancy to old age?
This affords room for many general observations concerning the gradual
change of our sentiments and inclinations, and the different maxims which
prevail in the different ages of human creatures. Even the characters,
which are peculiar to each individual, have a uniformity in their influence;
otherwise our acquaintance with the persons and our observation of their
conduct could never teach us their dispositions, or serve to direct our
behaviour with regard to them.
I grant it possible to find some actions,
which seem to have no regular connexion with any known motives, and are
exceptions to all the measures of conduct which have ever been established
for the government of men. But if we would willingly know what judgment
should be formed of such irregular and extraordinary actions, we may consider
the sentiments commonly entertained with regard to those irregular events
which appear in the course of nature, and the operations of external objects.
All causes are not conjoined to their usual effects with like uniformity.
An artificer, who handles only dead matter, may be disappointed of his
aim, as well as the politician, who directs the conduct of sensible and
intelligent agents.
The vulgar, who take things according to
their first appearance, attribute the uncertainty of events to such an
uncertainty in the causes as makes the latter often fail of their usual
influence; though they meet with no impediment in their operation. But
philosophers, observing that, almost in every part of nature, there is
contained a vast variety of springs and principles, which are hid, by reason
of their minuteness or remoteness, find, that it is at least possible the
contrariety of events may not proceed from any contingency in the cause,
but from the secret operation of contrary causes. This possibility is converted
into certainty by farther observation, when they remark that, upon an exact
scrutiny, a contrariety of effects always betrays a contrariety of causes,
and proceeds from their mutual opposition. A peasant can give no better
reason for the stopping of any clock or watch than to say that it does
not commonly go right: But an artist easily perceives that the same force
in the spring or pendulum has always the same influence on the wheels;
but fails of its usual effects, perhaps by reason of a grain of dust, which
puts a stop to the whole movement. From the observation of several parallel
instances, philosophers form a maxim that the connexion between all causes
and effects is equally necessary, and that its seeming uncertainty in some
instances proceeds from the secret opposition of contrary causes.
Thus, for instance, in the human body,
when the usual symptoms of health or sickness disappoint our expectation;
when medicines operate not with their wonted powers; when irregular events
follow from any particular cause; the philosopher and physician are not
surprised at the matter, nor are ever tempted to deny, in general, the
necessity and uniformity of those principles by which the animal economy
is conducted. They know that a human body is a mighty complicated machine:
That many secret powers lurk in it, which are altogether beyond our comprehension:
That to us it must often appear very uncertain in its operations: And that
therefore the irregular events, which outwardly discover themselves, can
be no proof that the laws of nature are not observed with the greatest
regularity in its internal operations and government.
The philosopher, if he be consistent, must
apply the same reasoning to the actions and volitions of intelligent agents.
The most irregular and unexpected resolutions of men may frequently be
accounted for by those who know every particular circumstance of their
character and situation. A person of an obliging disposition gives a peevish
answer: But he has the toothache, or has not dined. A stupid fellow discovers
an uncommon alacrity in his carriage: But he has met with a sudden piece
of good fortune. Or even when an action, as sometimes happens, cannot be
particularly accounted for, either by the person himself or by others;
we know, in general, that the characters of men are, to a certain degree,
inconstant and irregular. This is, in a manner, the constant character
of human nature; though it be applicable, in a more particular manner,
to some persons who have no fixed rule for their conduct, but proceed in
a continued course of caprice and inconstancy. The internal principles
and motives may operate in a uniform manner, notwithstanding these seeming
irregularities; in the same manner as the winds, rain, cloud, and other
variations of the weather are supposed to be governed by steady principles;
though not easily discoverable by human sagacity and enquiry.
Thus it appears, not only that the conjunction
between motives and voluntary actions is as regular and uniform as that
between the cause and effect in any part of nature; but also that this
regular conjunction has been universally acknowledged among mankind, and
has never been the subject of dispute, either in philosophy or common life.
Now, as it is from past experience that we draw all inferences concerning
the future, and as we conclude that objects will always be conjoined together
which we find to have always been conjoined; it may seem superfluous to
prove that this experienced uniformity in human actions is a source whence
we draw inferences concerning them. But in order to throw the argument
into a greater variety of lights we shall also insist, though briefly,
on this latter topic.
The mutual dependence of men is so great
in all societies that scarce any human action is entirely complete in itself,
or is performed without some reference to the actions of others, which
are requisite to make it answer fully the intention of the agent. The poorest
artificer, who labours alone, expects at least the protection of the magistrate,
to ensure him the enjoyment of the fruits of his labour. He also expects
that, when he carries his goods to market, and offers them at a reasonable
price, he shall find purchasers, and shall be able, by the money he acquires,
to engage others to supply him with those commodities which are requisite
for his subsistence. In proportion as men extend their dealings, and render
their intercourse with others more complicated, they always comprehend,
in their schemes of life, a greater variety of voluntary actions, which
they expect, from the proper motives, to co-operate with their own. In
all these conclusions they take their measures from past experience, in
the same manner as in their reasonings concerning external objects; and
firmly believe that men, as well as all the elements, are to continue,
in their operations, the same that they have ever found them. A manufacturer
reckons upon the labour of his servants for the execution of any work as
much as upon the tools which he employs, and would be equally surprised
were his expectations disappointed. In short, this experimental inference
and reasoning concerning the actions of others enters so much into human
life that no man, while awake, is ever a moment without employing it. Have
we not reason, therefore, to affirm that all mankind have always agreed
in the doctrine of necessity according to the foregoing definition and
explication of it?
Nor have philosophers even entertained
a different opinion from the people in this particular. For, not to mention
that almost every action of their life supposes that opinion, there are
even few of the speculative parts of learning to which it is not essential.
What would become of history, had we not a dependence on the veracity of
the historian according to the experience which we have had of mankind?
How could politics be a science, if laws and forms of government had not
a uniform influence upon society? Where would be the foundation of morals,
if particular characters had no certain or determinate power to produce
particular sentiments, and if these sentiments had no constant operation
on actions? And with what pretence could we employ our criticism upon any
poet or polite author, if we could not pronounce the conduct and sentiments
of his actors either natural or unnatural to such characters, and in such
circumstances? It seems almost impossible, therefore, to engage either
in science or action of any kind without acknowledging the doctrine of
necessity, and this inference from motive to voluntary actions, from characters
to conduct.
And indeed, when we consider how aptly
natural and moral evidence link together, and form only one chain of argument,
we shall make no scruple to allow that they are of the same nature, and
derived from the same principles. A prisoner who has neither money nor
interest, discovers the impossibility of his escape, as well when he considers
the obstinacy of the gaoler, as the walls and bars with which he is surrounded;
and, in all attempts for his freedom, chooses rather to work upon the stone
and iron of the one, than upon the inflexible nature of the other. The
same prisoner, when conducted to the scaffold, foresees his death as certainly
from the constancy and fidelity of his guards, as from the operation of
the axe or wheel. His mind runs along a certain train of ideas: the refusal
of the soldiers to consent to his escape; the action of the executioner;
the separation of the head and body; bleeding, convulsive motions, and
death. Here is a connected chain of natural causes and voluntary actions;
but the mind feels no difference between them in passing from one link
to another: Nor is it less certain of the future event than if it were
connected with the objects present to the memory or senses, by a train
of causes, cemented together by what we are pleased to call a physical
necessity. The same experienced union has the same effect on the mind,
whether the united objects be motives, volition, and actions; or figure
and motion. We may change the name of things; but their nature and their
operation on the understanding never change.
Were a man, whom I know to be honest and
opulent, and with whom I live in intimate friendship, to come into my house,
where I am surrounded with my servants, I rest assured that he is not to
stab me before he leaves it in order to rob me of my silver standish; and
I no more suspect this event than the falling of the house itself, which
is new, and solidly built and founded.--But he may have been seized with
a sudden and unknown frenzy.--So may a sudden earthquake arise, and shake
and tumble my house about my ears. I shall therefore change the suppositions.
I shall say that I know with certainty that he is not to put his hand into
the fire and hold it there till it be consumed: and this event, I think
I can foretell with the same assurance, as that, if he throw himself out
at the window, and meet with no obstruction, he will not remain a moment
suspended in the air. No suspicion of an unknown frenzy can give the least
possibility to the former event, which is so contrary to all the known
principles of human nature. A man who at noon leaves his purse full of
gold on the pavement at Charing-Cross, may as well expect that it will
fly away like a feather, as that he will find it untouched an hour after.
Above one half of human reasonings contain inferences of a similar nature,
attended with more or less degrees of certainty proportioned to our experience
of the usual conduct of mankind in such particular situations.
I have frequently considered, what could
possibly be the reason why all mankind, though they have ever, without
hesitation, acknowledged the doctrine of necessity in their whole practice
and reasoning, have yet discovered such a reluctance to acknowledge it
in words, and have rather shown a propensity, in all ages, to profess the
contrary opinion. The matter, I think, may be accounted for after the following
manner. If we examine the operations of body, and the production of effects
from their causes, we shall find that all our faculties can never carry
us farther in our knowledge of this relation than barely to observe that
particular objects are constantly conjoined together, and that the mind
is carried, by a customary transition, from the appearance of one to the
belief of the other. But though this conclusion concerning human ignorance
be the result of the strictest scrutiny of this subject, men still entertain
a strong propensity to believe that they penetrate farther into the powers
of nature, and perceive something like a necessary connexion between the
cause and the effect. When again they turn their reflections towards the
operations of their own minds, and feel no such connexion of the motive
and the action; they are thence apt to suppose, that there is a difference
between the effects which result from material force, and those which arise
from thought and intelligence. But being once convinced that we know nothing
farther of causation of any kind than merely the constant conjunction of
objects, and the consequent inference of the mind from one to another,
and finding that these two circumstances are universally allowed to have
place in voluntary actions; we may be more easily led to own the same necessity
common to all causes. And though this reasoning may contradict the systems
of many philosophers, in ascribing necessity to the determinations of the
will, we shall find, upon reflection, that they dissent from it in words
only, not in their real sentiment. Necessity, according to the sense in
which it is here taken, has never yet been rejected, nor can ever, I think,
be rejected by any philosopher. It may only, perhaps, be pretended that
the mind can perceive, in the operations of matter, some farther connexion
between the cause and effect; and connexion that has not place in voluntary
actions of intelligent beings. Now whether it be so or not, can only appear
upon examination; and it is incumbent on these philosophers to make good
their assertion, by defining or describing that necessity, and pointing
it out to us in the operations of material causes.
It would seem, indeed, that men begin at
the wrong end of this question concerning liberty and necessity, when they
enter upon it by examining the faculties of the soul, the influence of
the understanding, and the operations of the will. Let them first discuss
a more simple question, namely, the operations of body and of brute unintelligent
matter; and try whether they can there form any idea of causation and necessity,
except that of a constant conjunction of objects, and subsequent inference
of the mind from one to another. If these circumstances form, in reality,
the whole of that necessity, which we conceive in matter, and if these
circumstances be also universally acknowledged to take place in the operations
of the mind, the dispute is at an end; at least, must be owned to be thenceforth
merely verbal. But as long as we will rashly suppose, that we have some
farther idea of necessity and causation in the operations of external objects;
at the same time, that we can find nothing farther in the voluntary actions
of the mind; there is no possibility of bringing the question to any determinate
issue, while we proceed upon so erroneous a supposition. The only method
of undeceiving us is to mount up higher; to examine the narrow extent of
science when applied to material causes; and to convince ourselves that
all we know of them is the constant conjunction and inference above mentioned.
We may, perhaps, find that it is with difficulty we are induced to fix
such narrow limits to human understanding: but we can afterwards find no
difficulty when we come to apply this doctrine to the actions of the will.
For as it is evident that these have a regular conjunction with motives
and circumstances and characters, and as we always draw inferences from
one to the other, we must be obliged to acknowledge in words that necessity,
which we have already avowed, in every deliberation of our lives, and in
every step of our conduct and behaviour.[1]
But to proceed in this reconciling project
with regard to the question of liberty and necessity; the most contentious
question of metaphysics, the most contentious science; it will not require
many words to prove, that all mankind have ever agreed in the doctrine
of liberty as well as in that of necessity, and that the whole dispute,
in this respect also, has been hitherto merely verbal. For what is meant
by liberty, when applied to voluntary actions? We cannot surely mean that
actions have so little connexion with motives, inclinations, and circumstances,
that one does not follow with a certain degree of uniformity from the other,
and that one affords no inference by which we can conclude the existence
of the other. For these are plain and acknowledged matters of fact. By
liberty, then, we can only mean a power of acting or not acting, according
to the determinations of the will; this is, if we choose to remain at rest,
we may; if we choose to move, we also may. Now this hypothetical liberty
is universally allowed to belong to every one who is not a prisoner and
in chains. Here, then, is no subject of dispute.
Whatever definition we may give of liberty,
we should be careful to observe two requisite circumstances; First, that
it be consistent with plain matter of fact; secondly, that it be consistent
with itself. If we observe these circumstances, and render our definition
intelligible, I am persuaded that all mankind will be found of one opinion
with regard to it.
It is universally allowed that nothing
exists without a cause of its existence, and that chance, when strictly
examined, is a mere negative word, and means not any real power which has
anywhere a being in nature. But it is pretended that some causes are necessary,
some not necessary. Here then is the advantage of definitions. Let any
one define a cause, without comprehending, as a part of the definition,
a necessary connexion with its effect; and let him show distinctly the
origin of the idea, expressed by the definition; and I shall readily give
up the whole controversy. But if the foregoing explication of the matter
be received, this must be absolutely impracticable. Had not objects a regular
conjunction with each other, we should never have entertained any notion
of cause and effect; and this regular conjunction produces that inference
of the understanding, which is the only connexion, that we can have any
comprehension of. Whoever attempts a definition of cause, exclusive of
these circumstances, will be obliged either to employ unintelligible terms
or such as are synonymous to the term which he endeavours to define.[2]
And if the definition above mentioned be admitted; liberty, when opposed
to necessity, not to constraint, is the same thing with chance; which is
universally allowed to have no existence.
PART II
THERE is no method of reasoning more common,
and yet none more blameable, than, in philosophical disputes, to endeavour
the refutation of any hypothesis, by a pretence of its dangerous consequences
to religion and morality. When any opinion leads to absurdities, it is
certainly false; but it is not certain that an opinion is false, because
it is of dangerous consequence. Such topics, therefore, ought entirely
to be forborne; as serving nothing to the discovery of truth, but only
to make the person of an antagonist odious. This I observe in general,
without pretending to draw any advantage from it. I frankly submit to an
examination of this kind, and shall venture to affirm that the doctrines,
both of necessity and of liberty, as above explained, are not only consistent
with morality, but are absolutely essential to its support.
Necessity may be defined two ways, conformably
to the two definitions of cause, of which it makes an essential part. It
consists either in the constant conjunction of like objects, or in the
inference of the understanding from one object to another. Now necessity,
in both these senses, (which, indeed, are at bottom the same) has universally,
though tacitly, in the schools, in the pulpit, and in common life, been
allowed to belong to the will of man; and no one has ever pretended to
deny that we can draw inferences concerning human actions, and that those
inferences are founded on the experienced union of like actions, with like
motives, inclinations, and circumstances. The only particular in which
any one can differ, is, that either, perhaps, he will refuse to give the
name of necessity to this property of human actions: but as long as the
meaning is understood, I hope the word can do no harm: or that he will
maintain it possible to discover something farther in the operations of
matter. But this, it must be acknowledged, can be of no consequence to
morality or religion, whatever it may be to natural philosophy or metaphysics.
We may here be mistaken in asserting that there is no idea of any other
necessity or connexion in the actions of body: But surely we ascribe nothing
to the actions of the mind, but what everyone does, and must readily allow
of. We change no circumstance in the received orthodox system with regard
to the will, but only in that with regard to material objects and causes.
Nothing, therefore, can be more innocent, at least, than this doctrine.
All laws being founded on rewards and punishments,
it is supposed as a fundamental principle, that these motives have a regular
and uniform influence on the mind, and both produce the good and prevent
the evil actions. We may give to this influence what name we please; but,
as it is usually conjoined with the action, it must be esteemed a cause,
and be looked upon as an instance of that necessity, which we would here
establish.
The only proper object of hatred or vengeance
is a person or creature, endowed with thought and consciousness; and when
any criminal or injurious actions excite that passion, it is only by their
relation to the person, or connexion with him. Actions are, by their very
nature, temporary and perishing; and where they proceed not from some cause
in the character and disposition of the person who performed them, they
can neither redound to his honour, if good; nor infamy, if evil. The actions
themselves may be blameable; they may be contrary to all the rules of morality
and religion: but the person is not answerable for them; and as they proceeded
from nothing in him that is durable and constant, and leave nothing of
that nature behind them, it is impossible he can, upon their account, become
the object of punishment or vengeance. According to the principle, therefore,
which denies necessity, and consequently causes, a man is as pure and untainted,
after having committed the most horrid crime, as at the first moment of
his birth, nor is his character anywise concerned in his actions, since
they are not derived from it, and the wickedness of the one can never be
used as a proof of the depravity of the other.
Men are not blamed for such actions as
they perform ignorantly and casually, whatever may be the consequences.
Why? but because the principles of these actions are only momentary, and
terminate in them alone. Men are less blamed for such actions as they perform
hastily and unpremeditatedly than for such as proceed from deliberation.
For what reason? but because a hasty temper, though a constant cause or
principle in the mind, operates only by intervals, and infects not the
whole character. Again, repentance wipes off every crime, if attended with
a reformation of life and manners. How is this to be accounted for? but
by asserting that actions render a person criminal merely as they are proofs
of criminal principles in the mind; and when, by an alteration of these
principles, they cease to be just proofs, they likewise cease to be criminal.
But, except upon the doctrine of necessity, they never were just proofs,
and consequently never were criminal.
It will be equally easy to prove, and from
the same arguments, that liberty, according to that definition above mentioned,
in which all men agree, is also essential to morality, and that no human
actions, where it is wanting, are susceptible of any moral qualities, or
can be the objects either of approbation or dislike. For as actions are
objects of our moral sentiment, so far only as they are indications of
the internal character, passions, and affections; it is impossible that
they can give rise either to praise or blame, where they proceed not from
these principles, but are derived altogether from external violence.
I pretend not to have obviated or removed
all objections to this theory, with regard to necessity and liberty. I
can foresee other objections, derived from topics which have not here been
treated of. It may be said, for instance, that, if voluntary actions be
subjected to the same laws of necessity with the operations of matter,
there is a continued chain of necessary causes, pre-ordained and pre-determined,
reaching from the original cause of all to every single volition of every
human creature. No contingency anywhere in the universe; no indifference;
no liberty. While we act, we are, at the same time, acted upon. The ultimate
Author of all our volitions is the Creator of the world, who first bestowed
motion on this immense machine, and placed all beings in that particular
position, whence every subsequent event, by an inevitable necessity, must
result. Human actions, therefore, either can have no moral turpitude at
all, as proceeding from so good a cause; or if they have any turpitude,
they must involve our Creator in the same guilt, while he is acknowledged
to be their ultimate cause and author. For as a man, who fired a mine,
is answerable for all the consequences whether the train he employed be
long or short; so wherever a continued chain of necessary causes is fixed,
that Being, either finite or infinite, who produces the first, is likewise
the author of all the rest, and must both bear the blame and acquire the
praise which belong to them. Our clear and unalterable ideas of morality
establish this rule, upon unquestionable reasons, when we examine the consequences
of any human action; and these reasons must still have greater force when
applied to the volitions and intentions of a Being infinitely wise and
powerful. Ignorance or impotence may be pleaded for so limited a creature
as man; but those imperfections have no place in our Creator. He foresaw,
he ordained, he intended all those actions of men, which we so rashly pronounce
criminal. And we must therefore conclude, either that they are not criminal,
or that the Deity, not man, is accountable for them. But as either of these
positions is absurd and impious, it follows, that the doctrine from which
they are deduced cannot possibly be true, as being liable to all the same
objections. An absurd consequence, if necessary, proves the original doctrine
to be absurd; in the same manner as criminal actions render criminal the
original cause, if the connexion between them be necessary and inevitable.
This objection consists of two parts, which
we shall examine separately; First, that, if human actions can be traced
up, by a necessary chain, to the Deity, they can never be criminal; on
account of the infinite perfection of that Being from whom they are derived,
and who can intend nothing but what is altogether good and laudable. Or,
Secondly, if they be criminal, we must retract the attribute of perfection,
which we ascribe to the Deity, and must acknowledge him to be the ultimate
author of guilt and moral turpitude in all his creatures.
The answer to the first objection seems
obvious and convincing. There are many philosophers who, after an exact
scrutiny of all the phenomena of nature, conclude, that the WHOLE, considered
as one system, is, in every period of its existence, ordered with perfect
benevolence; and that the utmost possible happiness will, in the end, result
to all created beings, without any mixture of positive or absolute ill
or misery. Every physical ill, say they, makes an essential part of this
benevolent system, and could not possibly be removed, even by the Deity
himself, considered as a wise agent, without giving entrance to greater
ill, or excluding greater good, which will result from it. From this theory,
some philosophers, and the ancient Stoics among the rest, derived a topic
of consolation under all afflictions, while they taught their pupils that
those ills under which they laboured were, in reality, goods to the universe;
and that to an enlarged view, which could comprehend the whole system of
nature, every event became an object of joy and exultation. But though
this topic be specious and sublime, it was soon found in practice weak
and ineffectual. You would surely more irritate than appease a man lying
under the racking pains of the gout by preaching up to him the rectitude
of those general laws, which produced the malignant humours in his body,
and led them through the proper canals, to the sinews and nerves, where
they now excite such acute torments. These enlarged views may, for a moment,
please the imagination of a speculative man, who is placed in ease and
security; but neither can they dwell with constancy on his mind, even though
undisturbed by the emotions of pain or passion; much less can they maintain
their ground when attacked by such powerful antagonists. The affections
take a narrower and more natural survey of their object; and by an economy,
more suitable to the infirmity of human minds, regard alone the beings
around us, and are actuated by such events as appear good or ill to the
private system.
The case is the same with moral as with
physical ill. It cannot reasonably be supposed, that those remote considerations,
which are found of so little efficacy with regard to one, will have a more
powerful influence with regard to the other. The mind of man is so formed
by nature that, upon the appearance of certain characters, dispositions,
and actions, it immediately feels the sentiment of approbation or blame;
nor are there any emotions more essential to its frame and constitution.
The characters which engage our approbation are chiefly such as contribute
to the peace and security of human society; as the characters which excite
blame are chiefly such as tend to public detriment and disturbance: whence
it may reasonably be presumed, that the moral sentiments arise, either
mediately or immediately, from a reflection of these opposite interests.
What though philosophical meditations establish a different opinion or
conjecture; that everything is right with regard to the WHOLE, and that
the qualities, which disturb society, are, in the main, as beneficial,
and are as suitable to the primary intention of nature as those which more
directly promote its happiness and welfare? Are such remote and uncertain
speculations able to counterbalance the sentiments which arise from the
natural and immediate view of the objects? A man who is robbed of a considerable
sum; does he find his vexation for the loss anywise diminished by these
sublime reflections? Why then should his moral resentment against the crime
be supposed incompatible with them? Or why should not the acknowledgment
of a real distinction between vice and virtue be reconcileable to all speculative
systems of philosophy, as well as that of a real distinction between personal
beauty and deformity? Both these distinctions are founded in the natural
sentiments of the human mind: And these sentiments are not to be controuled
or altered by any philosophical theory or speculation whatsoever.
The second objection admits not of so easy
and satisfactory an answer; nor is it possible to explain distinctly, how
the Deity can be the mediate cause of all the actions of men, without being
the author of sin and moral turpitude. These are mysteries, which mere
natural and unassisted reason is very unfit to handle; and whatever system
she embraces, she must find herself involved in inextricable difficulties,
and even contradictions, at every step which she takes with regard to such
subjects. To reconcile the indifference and contingency of human actions
with prescience; or to defend absolute decrees, and yet free the Deity
from being the author of sin, has been found hitherto to exceed all the
power of philosophy. Happy, if she be thence sensible of her temerity,
when she pries into these sublime mysteries; and leaving a scene so full
of obscurities and perplexities, return, with suitable modesty, to her
true and proper province, the examination of common life; where she will
find difficulties enough to employ her enquiries, without launching into
so boundless an ocean of doubt, uncertainty, and contradiction!
[1] The prevalence of the doctrine of liberty
may be accounted for, from another cause, viz. a false sensation of seeming
experience which we have, or may have, of liberty or indifference, in many
of our actions. The necessity of any action, whether of matter or of mind,
is not, properly speaking, a quality in the agent, but in any thinking
or intelligent being, who may consider the action; and it consists chiefly
in the determination of his thoughts to infer the existence of that action
from some preceding objects; as liberty, when opposed to necessity, is
nothing but the want of that determination, and a certain looseness or
indifference, which we feel, in passing, or not passing, from the idea
of one object to that of any succeeding one. Now we may observe, that,
though, in reflecting on human actions, we seldom feel such a looseness,
or indifference, but are commonly able to infer them with considerable
certainty from their motives, and from the dispositions of the agent; yet
it frequently happens, that, in performing the actions themselves, we are
sensible of something like it: And as all resembling objects are readily
taken for each other, this has been employed as a demonstrative and even
intuitive proof of human liberty. We feel, that our actions are subject
to our will, on most occasions; and imagine we feel, that the will itself
is subject to nothing, because, when by a denial of it we are provoked
to try, we feel, that it moves easily every way, and produces an image
of itself (or a Velleity, as it is called in the schools) even on that
side, on which it did not settle. This image, or faint motion, we persuade
ourselves, could, at that time, have been compleated into the thing itself;
because, should that be denied, we find, upon a second trial, that, at
present, it can. We consider not, that the fantastical desire of shewing
liberty, is here the motive of our actions. And it seems certain, that,
however we may imagine we feel a liberty within ourselves, a spectator
can commonly infer our actions from our motives and character; and even
where he cannot, he concludes in general, that he might, were he perfectly
acquainted with every circumstance of our situation and temper, and the
most secret springs of our complexion and disposition. Now this is the
very essence of necessity, according to the foregoing doctrine.
[2] Thus, if a cause be defined, that which
produces any thing, it is easy to observe, that producing is synonymous
to causing. In like manner, if a cause be defined, that by which any thing
exists, this is liable to the same objection. For what is meant by these
words, by which? Had it been said, that a cause is that after which any
thing constantly exists; we should have understood the terms. For this
is, indeed, all we know of the matter. And this constantly forms the very
essence of necessity, nor have we any other idea of it.
SECTION IX: OF THE REASON
OF ANIMALS
ALL our reasonings concerning matter of fact
are founded on a species of Analogy, which leads us to expect from any
cause the same events, which we have observed to result from similar causes.
Where the causes are entirely similar, the analogy is perfect, and the
inference, drawn from it, is regarded as certain and conclusive: nor does
any man ever entertain a doubt, where he sees a piece of iron, that it
will have weight and cohesion of parts; as in all other instances, which
have ever fallen under his observation. But where the objects have not
so exact a similarity, the analogy is less perfect, and the inference is
less conclusive; though still it has some force, in proportion to the degree
of similarity and resemblance. The anatomical observations, formed upon
one animal, are, by this species of reasoning, extended to all animals;
and it is certain, that when the circulation of the blood, for instance,
is clearly proved to have place in one creature, as a frog, or fish, it
forms a strong presumption, that the same principle has place in all. These
analogical observations may be carried farther, even to this science, of
which we are now treating; and any theory, by which we explain the operations
of the understanding, or the origin and connexion of the passions in man,
will acquire additional authority, if we find, that the same theory is
requisite to explain the same phenomena in all other animals. We shall
make trial of this, with regard to the hypothesis, by which we have, in
the foregoing discourse, endeavoured to account for all experimental reasonings;
and it is hoped, that this new point of view will serve to confirm all
our former observations.
First, It seems evident, that animals as
well as men learn many things from experience, and infer, that the same
events will always follow from the same causes. By this principle they
become acquainted with the more obvious properties of external objects,
and gradually, from their birth, treasure up a knowledge of the nature
of fire, water, earth, stones, heights, depths, &c., and of the effects
which result from their operation. The ignorance and inexperience of the
young are here plainly distinguishable from the cunning and sagacity of
the old, who have learned, by long observation, to avoid what hurt them,
and to pursue what gave ease or pleasure. A horse, that has been accustomed
to the field, becomes acquainted with the proper height which he can leap,
and will never attempt what exceeds his force and ability. An old greyhound
will trust the more fatiguing part of the chace to the younger, and will
place himself so as to meet the hare in her doubles; nor are the conjectures,
which he forms on this occasion, founded in any thing but his observation
and experience.
This is still more evident from the effects
of discipline and education on animals, who, by the proper application
of rewards and punishments, may be taught any course of action, and most
contrary to their natural instincts and propensities. Is it not experience,
which renders a dog apprehensive of pain, when you menace him, or lift
up the whip to beat him? Is it not even experience, which makes him answer
to his name, and infer, from such an arbitrary sound, that you mean him
rather than any of his fellows, and intend to call him, when you pronounce
it in a certain manner, and with a certain tone and accent?
In all these cases, we may observe, that
the animal infers some fact beyond what immediately strikes his senses;
and that this inference is altogether founded on past experience, while
the creature expects from the present object the same consequences, which
it has always found in its observation to result from similar objects.
Secondly, It is impossible, that this inference
of the animal can be founded on any process of argument or reasoning, by
which he concludes, that like events must follow like objects, and that
the course of nature will always be regular in its operations. For if there
be in reality any arguments of this nature, they surely lie too abstruse
for the observation of such imperfect understandings; since it may well
employ the utmost care and attention of a philosophic genius to discover
and observe them. Animals, therefore are not guided in these inferences
by reasoning: neither are children; neither are the generality of mankind,
in their ordinary actions and conclusions: neither are philosophers themselves,
who, in all the active parts of life, are, in the main, the same with the
vulgar, and are governed by the same maxims. Nature must have provided
some other principle, of more ready, and more general use and application;
nor can an operation of such immense consequence in life, as that of inferring
effects from causes, be trusted to the uncertain process of reasoning and
argumentation. Were this doubtful with regard to men, it seems to admit
of no question with regard to the brute creation; and the conclusion being
once firmly established in the one, we have a strong presumption, from
all the rules of analogy, that it ought to be universally admitted, without
any exception or reserve. It is custom alone, which engages animals, from
every object, that strikes their senses, to infer its usual attendant,
and carries their imagination, from the appearance of the one, to conceive
the other, in that particular manner, which we denominate belief. No other
explication can be given of this operation, in all the higher, as well
as lower classes of sensitive beings, which fall under our notice and observation.[1]
But though animals learn many parts of
their knowledge from observation, there are also many parts of it, which
they derive from the original hand of nature; which much exceed the share
of capacity they possess on ordinary occasions; and in which they improve,
little or nothing, by the longest practice and experience. These we denominate
Instincts, and are so apt to admire as something very extraordinary, and
inexplicable by all the disquisitions of human understanding. But our wonder
will, perhaps, cease or diminish, when we consider, that the experimental
reasoning itself, which we possess in common with beasts, and on which
the whole conduct of life depends, is nothing but a species of instinct
or mechanical power, that acts in us unknown to ourselves; and in its chief
operations, is not directed by any such relations or comparisons of ideas,
as are the proper objects of our intellectual faculties. Though the instinct
be different, yet still it is an instinct, which teaches a man to avoid
the fire; as much as that, which teaches a bird, with such exactness, the
art of incubation, and the whole economy and order of its nursery.
[1] Since all reasoning concerning facts
or causes is derived merely from custom, it may be asked how it happens,
that men so much surpass animals in reasoning, and one man so much surpasses
another? Has not the same custom the same influence on all?
We shall here endeavour briefly to explain
the great difference in human understandings: After which the reason of
the difference between men and animals will easily be comprehended.
1. When we have lived any time, and have
been accustomed to the uniformity of nature, we acquire a general habit,
by which we always transfer the known to the unknown, and conceive the
latter to resemble the former. By means of this general habitual principle,
we regard even one experiment as the foundation of reasoning, and expect
a similar event with some degree of certainty, where the experiment has
been made accurately, and free from all foreign circumstances. It is therefore
considered as a matter of great importance to observe the consequences
of things; and as one man may very much surpass another in attention and
memory and observation, this will make a very great difference in their
reasoning.
2. Where there is a complication of causes
to produce any effect, one mind may be much larger than another, and better
able to comprehend the whole system of objects, and to infer justly their
consequences.
3. One man is able to carry on a chain
of consequences to a greater length than another.
4. Few men can think long without running
into a confusion of ideas, and mistaking one for another; and there are
various degrees of this infirmity.
5. The circumstance, on which the effect
depends, is frequently involved in other circumstances, which are foreign
and extrinsic. The separation of it often requires great attention, accuracy,
and subtility.
6. The forming of general maxims from particular
observation is a very nice operation; and nothing is more usual, from haste
or a narrowness of mind, which sees not on all sides, than to commit mistakes
in this particular.
7. When we reason from analogies, the man,
who has the greater experience or the greater promptitude of suggesting
analogies, will be the better reasoner.
8. Biases from prejudice, education, passion,
party, &c. hang more upon one mind than another.
9. After we have acquired a confidence
in human testimony, books and conversation enlarge much more the sphere
of one man's experience and thought than those of another.
It would be easy to discover many other
circumstances that make a difference in the understandings of men.
SECTION X: OF MIRACLES
PART I
THERE is, in Dr. Tillotson's writings, an
argument against the real presence, which is as concise, and elegant, and
strong as any argument can possibly be supposed against a doctrine, so
little worthy of a serious refutation. It is acknowledged on all hands,
says that learned prelate, that the authority, either of the scripture
or of tradition, is founded merely in the testimony of the Apostles, who
were eye-witnesses to those miracles of our Saviour, by which he proved
his divine mission. Our evidence, then, for, the truth of the Christian
religion is less than the evidence for the truth of our senses; because,
even in the first authors of our religion, it was no greater; and it is
evident it must diminish in passing from them to their disciples; nor can
any one rest such confidence in their testimony, as in the immediate object
of his senses. But a weaker evidence can never destroy a stronger; and
therefore, were the doctrine of the real presence ever so clearly revealed
in scripture, it were directly contrary to the rules of just reasoning
to give our assent to it. It contradicts sense, though both the scripture
and tradition, on which it is supposed to be built, carry not such evidence
with them as sense; when they are considered merely as external evidences,
and are not brought home to every one's breast, by the immediate operation
of the Holy Spirit.
Nothing is so convenient as a decisive
argument of this kind, which must at least silence the most arrogant bigotry
and superstition, and free us from their impertinent solicitations. I flatter
myself, that I have discovered an argument of a like nature, which, if
just, will, with the wise and learned, be an everlasting check to all kinds
of superstitious delusion, and consequently, will be useful as long as
the world endures. For so long, I presume, will the accounts of miracles
and prodigies be found in all history, sacred and profane.
Though experience be our only guide in
reasoning concerning matters of fact; it must be acknowledged, that this
guide is not altogether infallible, but in some cases is apt to lead us
into errors. One, who in our climate, should expect better weather in any
week of June than in one of December, would reason justly, and conformably
to experience; but it is certain, that he may happen, in the event, to
find himself mistaken. However, we may observe, that, in such a case, he
would have no cause to complain of experience; because it commonly informs
us beforehand of the uncertainty, by that contrariety of events, which
we may learn from a diligent observation. All effects follow not with like
certainty from their supposed causes. Some events are found, in all countries
and all ages, to have been constantly conjoined together: Others are found
to have been more variable, and sometimes to disappoint our expectations;
so that, in our reasonings concerning matter of fact, there are all imaginable
degrees of assurance, from the highest certainty to the lowest species
of moral evidence.
A wise man, therefore, proportions his
belief to the evidence. In such conclusions as are founded on an infallible
experience, he expects the event with the last degree of assurance, and
regards his past experience as a full proof of the future existence of
that event. In other cases, he proceeds with more caution: he weighs the
opposite experiments: he considers which side is supported by the greater
number of experiments: to that side he inclines, with doubt and hesitation;
and when at last he fixes his judgement, the evidence exceeds not what
we properly call probability. All probability, then, supposes an opposition
of experiments and observations, where the one side is found to overbalance
the other, and to produce a degree of evidence, proportioned to the superiority.
A hundred instances or experiments on one side, and fifty on another, afford
a doubtful expectation of any event; though a hundred uniform experiments,
with only one that is contradictory, reasonably beget a pretty strong degree
of assurance. In all cases, we must balance the opposite experiments, where
they are opposite, and deduct the smaller number from the greater, in order
to know the exact force of the superior evidence.
To apply these principles to a particular
instance; we may observe, that there is no species of reasoning more common,
more useful, and even necessary to human life, than that which is derived
from the testimony of men, and the reports of eye-witnesses and spectators.
This species of reasoning, perhaps, one may deny to be founded on the relation
of cause and effect. I shall not dispute about a word. It will be sufficient
to observe that our assurance in any argument of this kind is derived from
no other principle than our observation of the veracity of human testimony,
and of the usual conformity of facts to the reports of witnesses. It being
a general maxim, that no objects have any discoverable connexion together,
and that all the inferences, which we can draw from one to another, are
founded merely on our experience of their constant and regular conjunction;
it is evident, that we ought not to make an exception to this maxim in
favour of human testimony, whose connexion with any event seems, in itself,
as little necessary as any other. Were not the memory tenacious to a certain
degree; had not men commonly an inclination to truth and a principle of
probity; were they not sensible to shame, when detected in a falsehood:
were not these, I say, discovered by experience to be qualities, inherent
in human nature, we should never repose the least confidence in human testimony.
A man delirious, or noted for falsehood and villainy, has no manner of
authority with us.
And as the evidence, derived from witnesses
and human testimony, is founded on past experience, so it varies with the
experience, and is regarded either as a proof or a probability, according
as the conjunction between any particular kind of report and any kind of
object has been found to be constant or variable. There are a number of
circumstances to be taken into consideration in all judgements of this
kind; and the ultimate standard, by which we determine all disputes, that
may arise concerning them, is always derived from experience and observation.
Where this experience is not entirely uniform on any side, it is attended
with an unavoidable contrariety in our judgements, and with the same opposition
and mutual destruction of argument as in every other kind of evidence.
We frequently hesitate concerning the reports of others. We balance the
opposite circumstances, which cause any doubt or uncertainty; and when
we discover a superiority on any side, we incline to it; but still with
a diminution of assurance, in proportion to the force of its antagonist.
This contrariety of evidence, in the present
case, may be derived from several different causes; from the opposition
of contrary testimony; from the character or number of the witnesses; from
the manner of their delivering their testimony; or from the union of all
these circumstances. We entertain a suspicion concerning any matter of
fact, when the witnesses contradict each other; when they are but few,
or of a doubtful character; when they have an interest in what they affirm;
when they deliver their testimony with hesitation, or on the contrary,
with too violent asseverations. There are many other particulars of the
same kind, which may diminish or destroy the force of any argument, derived
from human testimony.
Suppose, for instance, that the fact, which
the testimony endeavours to establish, partakes of the extraordinary and
the marvellous; in that case, the evidence, resulting from the testimony,
admits of a diminution, greater or less, in proportion as the fact is more
or less unusual. The reason why we place any credit in witnesses and historians,
is not derived from any connexion, which we perceive a priori, between
testimony and reality, but because we are accustomed to find a conformity
between them. But when the fact attested is such a one as has seldom fallen
under our observation, here is a contest of two opposite experiences; of
which the one destroys the other, as far as its force goes, and the superior
can only operate on the mind by the force, which remains. The very same
principle of experience, which gives us a certain degree of assurance in
the testimony of witnesses, gives us also, in this case, another degree
of assurance against the fact, which they endeavour to establish; from
which contradiction there necessarily arises a counterpoize, and mutual
destruction of belief and authority.
I should not believe such a story were
it told me by Cato, was a proverbial saying in Rome, even during the lifetime
of that philosophical patriot.[1] The incredibility of a fact, it was allowed,
might invalidate so great an authority.
The Indian prince, who refused to believe
the first relations concerning the effects of frost, reasoned justly; and
it naturally required very strong testimony to engage his assent to facts,
that arose from a state of nature, with which he was unacquainted, and
which bore so little analogy to those events, of which he had had constant
and uniform experience. Though they were not contrary to his experience,
they were not conformable to it.[2]
But in order to encrease the probability
against the testimony of witnesses, let us suppose, that the fact, which
they affirm, instead of being only marvellous, is really miraculous; and
suppose also, that the testimony considered apart and in itself, amounts
to an entire proof; in that case, there is proof against proof, of which
the strongest must prevail, but still with a diminution of its force, in
proportion to that of its antagonist.
A miracle is a violation of the laws of
nature; and as a firm and unalterable experience has established these
laws, the proof against a miracle, from the very nature of the fact, is
as entire as any argument from experience can possibly be imagined. Why
is it more than probable, that all men must die; that lead cannot, of itself,
remain suspended in the air; that fire consumes wood, and is extinguished
by water; unless it be, that these events are found agreeable to the laws
of nature, and there is required a violation of these laws, or in other
words, a miracle to prevent them? Nothing is esteemed a miracle, if it
ever happen in the common course of nature. It is no miracle that a man,
seemingly in good health, should die on a sudden: because such a kind of
death, though more unusual than any other, has yet been frequently observed
to happen. But it is a miracle, that a dead man should come to life; because
that has never been observed in any age or country. There must, therefore,
be a uniform experience against every miraculous event, otherwise the event
would not merit that appellation. And as a uniform experience amounts to
a proof, there is here a direct and full proof, from the nature of the
fact, against the existence of any miracle; nor can such a proof be destroyed,
or the miracle rendered credible, but by an opposite proof, which is superior.[3]
The plain consequence is (and it is a general
maxim worthy of our attention), 'that no testimony is sufficient to establish
a miracle, unless the testimony be of such a kind, that its falsehood would
be more miraculous, than the fact, which it endeavors to establish; and
even in that case there is a mutual destruction of arguments, and the superior
only gives us an assurance suitable to that degree of force, which remains,
after deducting the inferior.' When anyone tells me, that he saw a dead
man restored to life, I immediately consider with myself, whether it be
more probable, that this person should either deceive or be deceived, or
that the fact, which he relates, should really have happened. I weigh the
one miracle against the other; and according to the superiority, which
I discover, I pronounce my decision, and always reject the greater miracle.
If the falsehood of his testimony would be more miraculous, than the event
which he relates; then, and not till then, can he pretend to command my
belief or opinion.
PART II
IN the foregoing reasoning we have supposed,
that the testimony, upon which a miracle is founded, may possibly amount
to an entire proof, and that the falsehood of that testimony would be a
real prodigy: but it is easy to show, that we have been a great deal too
liberal in our concession, and that there never was a miraculous event
established on so full an evidence.
For first, there is not to be found, in
all history, any miracle attested by a sufficient number of men, of such
unquestioned good-sense, education, and learning, as to secure us against
all delusion in themselves; of such undoubted integrity, as to place them
beyond all suspicion of any design to deceive others; of such credit and
reputation in the eyes of mankind, as to have a great deal to lose in case
of their being detected in any falsehood; and at the same time, attesting
facts performed in such a public manner and in so celebrated a part of
the world, as to render the detection unavoidable: all which circumstances
are requisite to give us a full assurance in the testimony of men.
Secondly. We may observe in human nature
a principle which, if strictly examined, will be found to diminish extremely
the assurance, which we might, from human testimony, have in any kind of
prodigy. The maxim, by which we commonly conduct ourselves in our reasonings,
is, that the objects, of which we have no experience, resembles those,
of which we have; that what we have found to be most usual is always most
probable; and that where there is an opposition of arguments, we ought
to give the preference to such as are founded on the greatest number of
past observations. But though, in proceeding by this rule, we readily reject
any fact which is unusual and incredible in an ordinary degree; yet in
advancing farther, the mind observes not always the same rule; but when
anything is affirmed utterly absurd and miraculous, it rather the more
readily admits of such a fact, upon account of that very circumstance,
which ought to destroy all its authority. The passion of surprise and wonder,
arising from miracles, being an agreeable emotion, gives a sensible tendency
towards the belief of those events, from which it is derived. And this
goes so far, that even those who cannot enjoy this pleasure immediately,
nor can believe those miraculous events, of which they are informed, yet
love to partake of the satisfaction at second-hand or by rebound, and place
a pride and delight in exciting the admiration of others.
With what greediness are the miraculous
accounts of travellers received, their descriptions of sea and land monsters,
their relations of wonderful adventures, strange men, and uncouth manners?
But if the spirit of religion join itself to the love of wonder, there
is an end of common sense; and human testimony, in these circumstances,
loses all pretensions to authority. A religionist may be an enthusiast,
and imagine he sees what has no reality: he may know his narrative to be
false, and yet persevere in it, with the best intentions in the world,
for the sake of promoting so holy a cause: or even where this delusion
has not place, vanity, excited by so strong a temptation, operates on him
more powerfully than on the rest of mankind in any other circumstances;
and self-interest with equal force. His auditors may not have, and commonly
have not, sufficient judgement to canvass his evidence: what judgement
they have, they renounce by principle, in these sublime and mysterious
subjects: or if they were ever so willing to employ it, passion and a heated
imagination disturb the regularity of its operations. their credulity increases
his impudence: and his impudence overpowers their credulity.
Eloquence, when at its highest pitch, leaves
little room for reason or reflection; but addressing itself entirely to
the fancy or the affections, captivates the willing hearers, and subdues
their understanding. Happily, this pitch it seldom attains. But what a
Tully or a Demosthenes could scarcely effect over a Roman or Athenian audience,
every Capuchin, every itinerant or stationary teacher can perform over
the generality of mankind, and in a higher degree, by touching such gross
and vulgar passions.
The many instances of forged miracles,
and prophecies, and supernatural events, which, in all ages, have either
been detected by contrary evidence, or which detect themselves by their
absurdity, prove sufficiently the strong propensity of mankind to the extraordinary
and the marvellous, and ought reasonably to beget a suspicion against all
relations of this kind. This is our natural way of thinking, even with
regard to the most common and most credible events. For instance: There
is no kind of report which rises so easily, and spreads so quickly, especially
in country places and provincial towns, as those concerning marriages;
insomuch that two young persons of equal condition never see each other
twice, but the whole neighbourhood immediately join them together. The
pleasure of telling a piece of news so interesting, of propagating it,
and of being the first reporters of it, spreads the intelligence. And this
is so well known, that no man of sense gives attention to these reports,
till he find them confirmed by some greater evidence. Do not the same passions,
and others still stronger, incline the generality of mankind to believe
and report, with the greatest vehemence and assurance, all religious miracles?
Thirdly. It forms a strong presumption
against all supernatural and miraculous relations, that they are observed
chiefly to abound among ignorant and barbarous nations; or if a civilized
people has ever given admission to any of them, that people will be found
to have received them from ignorant and barbarous ancestors, who transmitted
them with that inviolable sanction and authority, which always attend received
opinions. When we peruse the first histories of all nations, we are apt
to imagine ourselves transported into some new world; where the whole frame
of nature is disjointed, and every element performs its operations in a
different manner, from what it does at present. Battles, revolutions, pestilence,
famine and death, are never the effect of those natural causes, which we
experience. Prodigies, omens, oracles, judgements, quite obscure the few
natural events, that are intermingled with them. But as the former grow
thinner every page, in proportion as we advance nearer the enlightened
ages, we soon learn, that there is nothing mysterious or supernatural in
the case, but that all proceeds from the usual propensity of mankind towards
the marvellous, and that, though this inclination may at intervals receive
a check from sense and learning, it can never be thoroughly extirpated
from human nature.
It is strange, a judicious reader is apt
to say, upon the perusal of these wonderful historians, that such prodigious
events never happen in our days. But it is nothing strange, I hope, that
men should lie in all ages. You must surely have seen instances enough
of that frailty. You have yourself heard many such marvellous relations
started, which, being treated with scorn by all the wise and judicious,
have at last been abandoned even by the vulgar. Be assured, that those
renowned lies, which have spread and flourished to such a monstrous height,
arose from like beginnings; but being sown in a more proper soil, shot
up at last into prodigies almost equal to those which they relate.
It was a wise policy in that false prophet,
Alexander, who though now forgotten, was once so famous, to lay the first
scene of his impostures in Paphlagonia, where, as Lucian tells us, the
people were extremely ignorant and stupid, and ready to swallow even the
grossest delusion. People at a distance, who are weak enough to think the
matter at all worth enquiry, have no opportunity of receiving better information.
The stories come magnified to them by a hundred circumstances. Fools are
industrious in propagating the imposture; while the wise and learned are
contented, in general, to deride its absurdity, without informing themselves
of the particular facts, by which it may be distinctly refuted. And thus
the impostor above mentioned was enabled to proceed, from his ignorant
Paphlagonians, to the enlisting of votaries, even among the Grecian philosophers,
and men of the most eminent rank and distinction in Rome; nay, could engage
the attention of that sage emperor Marcus Aurelius; so far as to make him
trust the success of a military expedition to his delusive prophecies.
The advantages are so great, of starting
an imposture among an ignorant people, that, even though the delusion should
be too gross to impose on the generality of them (which, though seldom,
is sometimes the case) it has a much better chance for succeeding in remote
countries, than if the first scene had been laid in a city renowned for
arts and knowledge. The most ignorant and barbarous of these barbarians
carry the report abroad. None of their countrymen have a large correspondence,
or sufficient credit and authority to contradict and beat down the delusion.
Men's inclination to the marvellous has full opportunity to display itself.
And thus a story, which is universally exploded in the place where it was
first started, shall pass for certain at a thousand miles distance. But
had Alexander fixed his residence at Athens, the philosophers of that renowned
mart of learning had immediately spread, throughout the whole Roman empire,
their sense of the matter; which, being supported by so great authority,
and displayed by all the force of reason and eloquence, had entirely opened
the eyes of mankind. It is true; Lucian, passing by chance through Paphlagonia,
had an opportunity of performing this good office. But, though much to
be wished, it does not always happen, that every Alexander meets with a
Lucian, ready to expose and detect his impostures.
I may add as a fourth reason, which diminishes
the authority of prodigies, that there is no testimony for any, even those
which have not been expressly detected, that is not opposed by an infinite
number of witnesses; so that not only the miracle destroys the credit of
testimony, but the testimony destroys itself. To make this the better understood,
let us consider, that, in matters of religion, whatever is different is
contrary; and that it is impossible the religions of ancient Rome, of Turkey,
of Siam, and of China should, all of them, be established on any solid
foundation. Every miracle, therefore, pretended to have been wrought in
any of these religions (and all of them abound in miracles), as its direct
scope is to establish the particular system to which it is attributed;
so has it the same force, though more indirectly, to overthrow every other
system. In destroying a rival system, it likewise destroys the credit of
those miracles, on which that system was established; so that all the prodigies
of different religions are to be regarded as contrary facts, and the evidences
of these prodigies, whether weak or strong, as opposite to each other.
According to this method of reasoning, when we believe any miracle of Mahomet
or his successors, we have for our warrant the testimony of a few barbarous
Arabians: and on the other hand, we are to regard the authority of Titus
Livius, Plutarch, Tacitus, and, in short, of all the authors and witnesses,
Grecian, Chinese, and Roman Catholic, who have related any miracle in their
particular religion; I say, we are to regard their testimony in the same
light as if they had mentioned that Mahometan miracle, and had in express
terms contradicted it, with the same certainty as they have for the miracle
they relate. This argument may appear over subtile and refined; but is
not in reality different from the reasoning of a judge, who supposes, that
the credit of two witnesses, maintaining a crime against any one, is destroyed
by the testimony of two others, who affirm him to have been two hundred
leagues distant, at the same instant when the crime is said to have been
committed.
One of the best attested miracles in all
profane history, is that which Tacitus reports of Vespasian, who cured
a blind man in Alexandria, by means of his spittle, and a lame man by the
mere touch of his foot; in obedience to a vision of the god Serapis, who
had enjoined them to have recourse to the Emperor, for these miraculous
cures. The story may be seen in that fine historian[4]; where every circumstance
seems to add weight to the testimony, and might be displayed at large with
all the force of argument and eloquence, if any one were now concerned
to enforce the evidence of that exploded and idolatrous superstition. The
gravity, solidity, age, and probity of so great an emperor, who, through
the whole course of his life, conversed in a familiar manner with his friends
and courtiers, and never affected those extraordinary airs of divinity
assumed by Alexander and Demetrius. The historian, a contemporary writer,
noted for candour and veracity, and withal, the greatest and most penetrating
genius, perhaps, of all antiquity; and so free from any tendency to credulity,
that he even lies under the contrary imputation, of atheism and profaneness:
The persons, from whose authority he related the miracle, of established
character for judgement and veracity, as we may well presume; eye-witnesses
of the fact, and confirming their testimony, after the Flavian family was
despoiled of the empire, and could no longer give any reward, as the price
of a lie. Utrumque, qui interfuere, nunc quoque memorant, postquam nullum
mendacio pretium. To which if we add the public nature of the facts, as
related, it will appear, that no evidence can well be supposed stronger
for so gross and so palpable a falsehood.
There is also a memorable story related
by Cardinal de Retz, which may well deserve our consideration. When that
intriguing politician fled into Spain, to avoid the persecution of his
enemies, he passed through Saragossa, the capital of Arragon, where he
was shewn, in the cathedral, a man, who had served seven years as a doorkeeper,
and was well known to every body in town, that had ever paid his devotions
at that church. He had been seen, for so long a time, wanting a leg; but
recovered that limb by the rubbing of holy oil upon the stump; and the
cardinal assures us that he saw him with two legs. This miracle was vouched
by all the canons of the church; and the whole company in town were appealed
to for a confirmation of the fact; whom the cardinal found, by their zealous
devotion, to be thorough believers of the miracle. Here the relater was
also contemporary to the supposed prodigy, of an incredulous and libertine
character, as well as of great genius; the miracle of so singular a nature
as could scarcely admit of a counterfeit, and the witnesses very numerous,
and all of them, in a manner, spectators of the fact, to which they gave
their testimony. And what adds mightily to the force of the evidence, and
may double our surprise on this occasion, is, that the cardinal himself,
who relates the story, seems not to give any credit to it, and consequently
cannot be suspected of any concurrence in the holy fraud. He considered
justly, that it was not requisite, in order to reject a fact of this nature,
to be able accurately to disprove the testimony, and to trace its falsehood,
through all the circumstances of knavery and credulity which produced it.
He knew, that, as this was commonly altogether impossible at any small
distance of time and place; so was it extremely difficult, even where one
was immediately present, by reason of the bigotry, ignorance, cunning,
and roguery of a great part of mankind. He therefore concluded, like a
just reasoner, that such an evidence carried falsehood upon the very face
of it, and that a miracle, supported by any human testimony, was more properly
a subject of derision than of argument.
There surely never was a greater number
of miracles ascribed to one person, than those, which were lately said
to have been wrought in France upon the tomb of Abbe Paris, the famous
Jansenist, with whose sanctity the people were so long deluded. The curing
of the sick, giving hearing to the deaf, and sight to the blind, were every
where talked of as the usual effects of that holy sepulchre. But what is
more extraordinary; many of the miracles were immediately proved upon the
spot, before judges of unquestioned integrity, attested by witnesses of
credit and distinction, in a learned age, and on the most eminent theatre
that is now in the world. Nor is this all: a relation of them was published
and dispersed everywhere; nor were the Jesuits, though a learned body supported
by the civil magistrate, and determined enemies to those opinions, in whose
favour the miracles were said to have been wrought, ever able distinctly
to refute or detect them.[5] Where shall we find such a number of circumstances,
agreeing to the corroboration of one fact? And what have we to oppose to
such a cloud of witnesses, but the absolute impossibility or miraculous
nature of the events, which they relate? And this surely, in the eyes of
all reasonable people, will alone be regarded as a sufficient refutation.
Is the consequence just, because some human
testimony has the utmost force and authority in some cases, when it relates
the battle of Philippi or Pharsalia for instance; that therefore all kinds
of testimony must, in all cases, have equal force and authority? Suppose
that the Caesarean and Pompeian factions had, each of them, claimed the
victory in these battles, and that the historians of each party had uniformly
ascribed the advantage to their own side; how could mankind, at this distance,
have been able to determine between them? The contrariety is equally strong
between the miracles related by Herodotus or Plutarch, and those delivered
by Mariana, Bede, or any monkish historian.
The wise lend a very academic faith to
every report which favours the passion of the reporter; whether it magnifies
his country, his family, or himself, or in any other way strikes in with
his natural inclinations and propensities. But what greater temptation
than to appear a missionary, a prophet, an ambassador from heaven? Who
would not encounter many dangers and difficulties, in order to attain so
sublime a character? Or if, by the help of vanity and a heated imagination,
a man has first made a convert of himself, and entered seriously into the
delusion; who ever scruples to make use of pious frauds, in support of
so holy and meritorious a cause?
The smallest spark may here kindle into
the greatest flame; because the materials are always prepared for it. The
avidum genus auricularum[6], the gazing populace, receive greedily, without
examination, whatever sooths superstition, and promotes wonder.
How many stories of this nature have, in
all ages, been detected and exploded in their infancy? How many more have
been celebrated for a time, and have afterwards sunk into neglect and oblivion?
Where such reports, therefore, fly about, the solution of the phenomenon
is obvious; and we judge in conformity to regular experience and observation,
when we account for it by the known and natural principles of credulity
and delusion. And shall we, rather than have a recourse to so natural a
solution, allow of a miraculous violation of the most established laws
of nature?
I need not mention the difficulty of detecting
a falsehood in any private or even public history, at the place, where
it is said to happen; much more when the scene is removed to ever so small
a distance. Even a court of judicature, with all the authority, accuracy,
and judgement, which they can employ, find themselves often at a loss to
distinguish between truth and falsehood in the most recent actions. But
the matter never comes to any issue, if trusted to the common method of
altercations and debate and flying rumours; especially when men's passions
have taken part on either side.
In the infancy of new religions, the wise
and learned commonly esteem the matter too inconsiderable to deserve their
attention or regard. And when afterwards they would willingly detect the
cheat in order to undeceive the deluded multitude, the season is now past,
and the records and witnesses, which might clear up the matter, have perished
beyond recovery.
No means of detection remain, but those
which must be drawn from the very testimony itself of the reporters: and
these, though always sufficient with the judicious and knowing, are commonly
too fine to fall under the comprehension of the vulgar.
Upon the whole, then, it appears, that
no testimony for any kind of miracle has ever amounted to a probability,
much less to a proof; and that, even supposing it amounted to a proof,
it would be opposed by another proof; derived from the very nature of the
fact, which it would endeavour to establish. It is experience only, which
gives authority to human testimony; and it is the same experience, which
assures us of the laws of nature. When, therefore, these two kinds of experience
are contrary, we have nothing to do but subtract the one from the other,
and embrace an opinion, either on one side or the other, with that assurance
which arises from the remainder. But according to the principle here explained,
this subtraction, with regard to all popular religions, amounts to an entire
annihilation; and therefore we may establish it as a maxim, that no human
testimony can have such force as to prove a miracle, and make it a just
foundation for any such system of religion.
I beg the limitations here made may be
remarked, when I say, that a miracle can never be proved, so as to be the
foundation of a system of religion. For I own, that otherwise, there may
possibly be miracles, or violations of the usual course of nature, of such
a kind as to admit of proof from human testimony; though, perhaps, it will
be impossible to find any such in all the records of history. Thus, suppose,
all authors, in all languages, agree, that, from the first of January,
1600, there was a total darkness over the whole earth for eight days: suppose
that the tradition of this extraordinary event is still strong and lively
among the people: that all travellers, who return from foreign countries,
bring us accounts of the same tradition, without the least variation or
contradiction: it is evident, that our present philosophers, instead of
doubting the fact, ought to receive it as certain, and ought to search
for the causes whence it might be derived. The decay, corruption, and dissolution
of nature, is an event rendered probable by so many analogies, that any
phenomenon, which seems to have a tendency towards that catastrophe, comes
within the reach of human testimony, if that testimony be very extensive
and uniform.
But suppose, that all the historians who
treat of England, should agree, that, on the first of January, 1600, Queen
Elizabeth died; that both before and after her death she was seen by her
physicians and the whole court, as is usual with persons of her rank; that
her successor was acknowledged and proclaimed by the parliament; and that,
after being interred a month, she again appeared, resumed the throne, and
governed England for three years: I must confess that I should be surprised
at the concurrence of so many odd circumstances, but should not have the
least inclination to believe so miraculous an event. I should not doubt
of her pretended death, and of those other public circumstances that followed
it: I should only assert it to have been pretended, and that it neither
was, nor possibly could be real. You would in vain object to me the difficulty,
and almost impossibility of deceiving the world in an affair of such consequence;
the wisdom and solid judgment of that renowned queen; with the little or
no advantage which she could reap from so poor an artifice: all this might
astonish me; but I would still reply, that the knavery and folly of men
are such common phenomena, that I should rather believe the most extraordinary
events to arise from their concurrence, than admit of so signal a violation
of the laws of nature.
But should this miracle be ascribed to
any new system of religion; men, in all ages, have been so much imposed
on by ridiculous stories of that kind, that this very circumstance would
be a full proof of a cheat, and sufficient, with all men of sense, not
only to make them reject the fact, but even reject it without farther examination.
Though the Being to whom the miracle is ascribed, be, in this case, Almighty,
it does not, upon that account, become a whit more probable; since it is
impossible for us to know the attributes or actions of such a Being, otherwise
than from the experience which we have of his productions, in the usual
course of nature. This still reduces us to past observation, and obliges
us to compare the instances of the violation of truth in the testimony
of men, with those of the violation of the laws of nature by miracles,
in order to judge which of them is most likely and probable. As the violations
of truth are more common in the testimony concerning religious miracles,
than in that concerning any other matter of fact; this must diminish very
much the authority of the former testimony, and make us form a general
resolution, never to lend any attention to it, with whatever specious pretence
it may be covered.
Lord Bacon seems to have embraced the same
principles of reasoning. 'We ought,' says he, 'to make a collection or
particular history of all monsters and prodigious births or productions,
and in a word of every thing new, rare, and extraordinary in nature. But
this must be done with the most severe scrutiny, lest we depart from truth.
Above all, every relation must be considered as suspicious, which depends
in any degree upon religion, as the prodigies of Livy: and no less so,
everything that is to be found in the writers of natural magic or alchimy,
or such authors, who seem, all of them, to have an unconquerable appetite
for falsehood and fable.[7]
I am the better pleased with the method
of reasoning here delivered, as I think it may serve to confound those
dangerous friends or disguised enemies to the Christian Religion, who have
undertaken to defend it by the principles of human reason. Our most holy
religion is founded on Faith, not on reason; and it is a sure method of
exposing it to put it to such a trial as it is, by no means, fitted to
endure. To make this more evident, let us examine those miracles, related
in scripture; and not to lose ourselves in too wide a field, let us confine
ourselves to such as we find in the Pentateuch, which we shall examine,
according to the principles of these pretended Christians, not as the word
or testimony of God himself, but as the production of a mere human writer
and historian. Here then we are first to consider a book, presented to
us by a barbarous and ignorant people, written in an age when they were
still more barbarous, and in all probability long after the facts which
it relates, corroborated by no concurring testimony, and resembling those
fabulous accounts, which every nation gives of its origin. Upon reading
this book, we find it full of prodigies and miracles. It gives an account
of a state of the world and of human nature entirely different from the
present: of our fall from that state: of the age of man, extended to near
a thousand years: of the destruction of the world by a deluge: of the arbitrary
choice of one people, as the favourites of heaven; and that people the
countrymen of the author: of their deliverance from bondage by prodigies
the most astonishing imaginable: I desire any one to lay his hand upon
his heart, and after a serious consideration declare, whether he thinks
that the falsehood of such a book, supported by such a testimony, would
be more extraordinary and miraculous than all the miracles it relates;
which is, however, necessary to make it be received, according to the measures
of probability above established.
What we have said of miracles may be applied,
without any variation, to prophecies; and indeed, all prophecies are real
miracles, and as such only, can be admitted as proofs of any revelation.
If it did not exceed the capacity of human nature to foretell future events,
it would be absurd to employ any prophecy as an argument for a divine mission
or authority from heaven. So that, upon the whole, we may conclude, that
the Christian Religion not only was at first attended with miracles, but
even at this day cannot be believed by any reasonable person without one.
Mere reason is insufficient to convince us of its veracity: and whoever
is moved by Faith to assent to it, is conscious of a continued miracle
in his own person, which subverts all the principles of his understanding,
and gives him a determination to believe what is most contrary to custom
and experience.
[1] Plutarch, in vita Catonis.
[2] No Indian, it is evident, could have
experience that water did not freeze in cold climates. This is placing
nature in a situation quite unknown to him; and it is impossible for him
to tell a priori what will result from it. It is making a new experiment,
the consequence of which is always uncertain. One may sometimes conjecture
from analogy what will follow; but still this is but conjecture. And it
must be confessed, that, in the present case of freezing, the event follows
contrary to the rules of analogy, and is such as a rational Indian would
not look for. The operations of cold upon water are not gradual, according
to the degrees of cold; but whenever it comes to the freezing point, the
water passes in a moment, from the utmost liquidity to perfect hardness.
Such an event, therefore, may be denominated extraordinary, and requires
a pretty strong testimony, to render it credible to people in a warm climate:
But still it is not miraculous, nor contrary to uniform experience of the
course of nature in cases where all the circumstances are the same. The
inhabitants of Sumatra have always seen water fluid in their own climate,
and the freezing of their rivers ought to be deemed a prodigy: But they
never saw water in Muscovy during the winter; and therefore they cannot
reasonably be positive what would there be the consequence.
[3] Sometimes an event may not, in itself,
seem to be contrary to the laws of nature, and yet, if it were real, it
might, by reason of some circumstances, be denominated a miracle; because,
in fact, it is contrary to these laws. Thus if a person, claiming a divine
authority, should command a sick person to be well, a healthful man to
fall down dead, the clouds to pour rain, the winds to blow, in short, should
order many natural events, which immediately follow upon his command; these
might justly be esteemed miracles, because they are really, in this case,
contrary to the laws of nature. For if any suspicion remain, that the event
and command concurred by accident there is no miracle and no transgression
of the laws of nature. If this suspicion be removed, there is evidently
a miracle, and a transgression of these laws; because nothing can be more
contrary to nature than that the voice or command of a man should have
such an influence. A miracle may be accurately defined, a transgression
of a law of nature by a particular volition of the Deity, or by the interposition
of some invisible agent. A miracle may either be discoverable by men or
not. This alters not its nature and essence. The raising of a house or
ship into the air is a visible miracle. The raising of a feather, when
the wind wants ever so little of a force requisite for that purpose, is
as real a miracle, though not so sensible with regard to us.
[4] Hist. lib. v. cap. 8, Suetonius gives
nearly the same account in vita Vesp.
[5] By Mons. Montgeron, counsellor or judge
of the Parliament of Paris.
[6] Lucret.
[7] Nov. Org. lib. ii. aph. 29.
SECTION XI: OF A PARTICULAR
PROVIDENCE AND OF A FUTURE STATE
I WAS lately engaged in conversation with
a friend who loves sceptical paradoxes; where, though he advanced many
principles, of which I can by no means approve, yet as they seem to be
curious, and to bear some relation to the chain of reasoning carried on
throughout this enquiry, I shall here copy them from my memory as accurately
as I can, in order to submit them to the judgement of the reader.
Our conversation began with my admiring
the singular good fortune of philosophy, which, as it requires entire liberty
above all other privileges, and chiefly flourishes from the free opposition
of sentiments and argumentation, received its first birth in an age and
country of freedom and toleration, and was never cramped, even in its most
extravagant principles, by any creeds, concessions, or penal statutes.
For, except the banishment of Protagoras, and the death of Socrates, which
last event proceeded partly from other motives, there are scarcely any
instances to be met with, in ancient history, of this bigoted jealousy,
with which the present age is so much infested. Epicurus lived at Athens
to an advanced age, in peace and tranquillity: Epicureans[1] were even
admitted to receive the sacerdotal character, and to officiate at the altar,
in the most sacred rites of the established religion: and the public encouragement[2]
of pensions and salaries was afforded equally, by the wisest of all the
Roman emperors[3], to the professors of every sect of philosophy. How requisite
such kind of treatment was to philosophy, in her early youth, will easily
be conceived, if we reflect, that, even at present, when she may be supposed
more hardy and robust, she bears with much difficulty the inclemency of
the seasons, and those harsh winds of calumny and persecution, which blow
upon her.
You admire, says my friend, as the singular
good fortune of philosophy, what seems to result from the natural course
of things, and to be unavoidable in every age and nation. This pertinacious
bigotry, of which you complain, as so fatal to philosophy, is really her
offspring, who, after allying with superstition, separates himself entirely
from the interest of his parent, and becomes her most inveterate enemy
and persecutor. Speculative dogmas of religion, the present occasions of
such furious dispute, could not possibly be conceived or admitted in the
early ages of the world; when mankind, being wholly illiterate, formed
an idea of religion more suitable to their weak apprehension, and composed
their sacred tenets of such tales chiefly as were the objects of traditional
belief, more than of argument or disputation. After the first alarm, therefore,
was over, which arose from the new paradoxes and principles of the philosophers;
these teachers seem ever after, during the ages of antiquity, to have lived
in great harmony with the established superstition, and to have made a
fair partition of mankind between them; the former claiming all the learned
and wise, the latter possessing all the vulgar and illiterate.
It seems then, say I, that you leave politics
entirely out of the question, and never suppose, that a wise magistrate
can justly be jealous of certain tenets of philosophy, such as those of
Epicurus, which, denying a divine existence, and consequently a providence
and a future state, seem to loosen, in a great measure the ties of morality,
and may be supposed, for that reason, pernicious to the peace of civil
society.
I know, replied he, that in fact these
persecutions never, in any age, proceeded from calm reason, or from experience
of the pernicious consequences of philosophy; but arose entirely from passion
and prejudice. But what if I should advance farther, and assert, that if
Epicurus had been accused before the people, by any of the sycophants or
informers of those days, he could easily have defended his cause, and proved
his principles of philosophy to be as salutary as those of his adversaries,
who endeavoured, with such zeal, to expose him to the public hatred and
jealousy?
I wish, said I, you would try your eloquence
upon so extraordinary a topic, and make a speech for Epicurus, which might
satisfy, not the mob of Athens, if you will allow that ancient and polite
city to have contained any mob, but the more philosophical part of his
audience, such as might be supposed capable of comprehending his arguments.
The matter would not be difficult, upon
such conditions, replied he: and if you please, I shall suppose myself
Epicurus for a moment, and make you stand for the Athenian people, and
shall deliver you such an harangue as will fill all the urn with white
beans, and leave not a black one to gratify the malice of my adversaries.
Very well: pray proceed upon these suppositions.
I come hither, O ye Athenians, to justify
in your assembly what I maintain in my school, and I find myself impeached
by furious antagonists, instead of reasoning with calm and dispassionate
enquirers. Your deliberations, which of right should be directed to questions
of public good, and the interest of the commonwealth, are diverted to the
disquisitions of speculative philosophy; and these magnificent, but perhaps
fruitless enquiries, take place of your more familiar but more useful occupations.
But so far as in me lies, I will prevent this abuse. We shall not here
dispute concerning the origin and government of worlds. We shall only enquire
how far such questions concern the public interest. And if I can persuade
you, that they are entirely indifferent to the peace of society and security
of government, I hope that you will presently send us back to our schools,
there to examine, at leisure, the question the most sublime, but, at the
same time, the most speculative of all philosophy.
The religious philosophers, not satisfied
with the tradition of your forefathers, and doctrine of your priests (in
which I willingly acquiesce), indulge a rash curiosity, in trying how far
they can establish religion upon the principles of reason; and they thereby
excite, instead of satisfying, the doubts, which naturally arise from a
diligent and scrutinous enquiry. They paint, in the most magnificent colours,
the order, beauty, and wise arrangement of the universe; and then ask,
if such a glorious display of intelligence could proceed from the fortuitous
concourse of atoms, or if chance could produce what the greatest genius
can never sufficiently admire. I shall not examine the justness of this
argument. I shall allow it to be as solid as my antagonists and accusers
can desire. It is sufficient, if I can prove, from this very reasoning,
that the question is entirely speculative, and that, when, in my philosophical
disquisitions, I deny a providence and a future state, I undermine not
the foundations of society, but advance principles, which they themselves,
upon their own topics, if they argue consistently, must allow to be solid
and satisfactory.
You then, who are my accusers, have acknowledged,
that the chief or sole argument for a divine existence (which I never questioned)
is derived from the order of nature; where there appear such marks of intelligence
and design, that you think it extravagant to assign for its cause, either
chance, or the blind and unguided force of matter. You allow, that this
is an argument drawn from effects to causes. >From the order of the work,
you infer, that there must have been project and forethought in the workman.
If you cannot make out this point, you allow, that your conclusion fails;
and you pretend not to establish the conclusion in a greater latitude than
the phenomena of nature will justify. These are your concessions. I desire
you to mark the consequences.
When we infer any particular cause from
an effect, we must proportion the one to the other, and can never be allowed
to ascribe to the cause any qualities, but what are exactly sufficient
to produce the effect. A body of ten ounces raised in any scale may serve
as a proof, that the counterbalancing weight exceeds ten ounces; but can
never afford a reason that it exceeds a hundred. If the cause, assigned
for any effect, be not sufficient to produce it, we must either reject
that cause, or add to it such qualities as will give it a just proportion
to the effect. But if we ascribe to it farther qualities, or affirm it
capable of producing other effects, we can only indulge the licence of
conjecture, and arbitrarily suppose the existence of qualities and energies,
without reason or authority.
The same rule holds, whether the cause
assigned be brute unconscious matter, or a rational intelligent being.
If the cause be known only by the effect, we never ought to ascribe to
it any qualities, beyond what are precisely requisite to produce the effect:
nor can we, by any rules of just reasoning, return back from the cause,
and infer other effects from it, beyond those by which alone it is known
to us. No one, merely from the sight of one of Zeuxis's pictures, could
know, that he was also a statuary or architect, and was an artist no less
skilful in stone and marble than in colours. The talents and taste, displayed
in the particular work before us; these we may safely conclude the workman
to be possessed of. The cause must be proportioned to the effect; and if
we exactly and precisely proportion it, we shall never find in it any qualities,
that point farther, or afford an inference concerning any other design
or performance. Such qualities must be somewhat beyond what is merely requisite
for producing the effect, which we examine.
Allowing, therefore, the gods to be the
authors of the existence or order of the universe; it follows, that they
possess that precise degree of power, intelligence, and benevolence, which
appears in their workmanship; but nothing farther can ever be proved, except
we call in the assistance of exaggeration and flattery to supply the defects
of argument and reasoning. So far as the traces of any attributes, at present,
appear, so far may we conclude these attributes to exist. The supposition
of farther attributes is mere hypothesis; much more the supposition, that,
in distant regions of space or periods of time, there has been, or will
be, a more magnificent display of these attributes, and a scheme of administration
more suitable to such imaginary virtues. We can never be allowed to mount
up from the universe, the effect, to Jupiter, the cause; and then descend
downwards, to infer any new effect from that cause; as if the present effects
alone were not entirely worthy of the glorious attributes, which we ascribe
to that deity. The knowledge of the cause being derived solely from the
effect, they must be exactly adjusted to each other; and the one can never
refer to anything farther, or be the foundation of any new inference and
conclusion.
You find certain phenomena in nature. You
seek a cause or author. You imagine that you have found him. You afterwards
become so enamoured of this offspring of your brain, that you imagine it
impossible, but he must produce something greater and more perfect than
the present scene of things, which is so full of ill and disorder. You
forget, that this superlative intelligence and benevolence are entirely
imaginary, or, at least, without any foundation in reason; and that you
have no ground to ascribe to him any qualities, but what you see he has
actually exerted and displayed in his productions. Let your gods, therefore,
O philosophers, be suited to the present appearances of nature: and presume
not to alter these appearances by arbitrary suppositions, in order to suit
them to the attributes, which you so fondly ascribe to your deities.
When priests and poets, supported by your
authority, O Athenians, talk of a golden or silver age, which preceded
the present state of vice and misery, I hear them with attention and with
reverence. But when philosophers, who pretend to neglect authority, and
to cultivate reason, hold the same discourse, I pay them not, I own, the
same obsequious submission and pious deference. I ask; who carried them
into the celestial regions, who admitted them into the councils of the
gods, who opened to them the book of fate, that they thus rashly affirm,
that their deities have executed, or will execute, any purpose beyond what
has actually appeared? If they tell me, that they have mounted on the steps
or by the gradual ascent of reason, and by drawing inferences from effects
to causes, I still insist, that they have aided the ascent of reason by
the wings of imagination; otherwise they could not thus change their manner
of inference, and argue from causes to effects; presuming, that a more
perfect production than the present world would be more suitable to such
perfect beings as the gods, and forgetting that they have no reason to
ascribe to these celestial beings any perfection or any attribute, but
what can be found in the present world.
Hence all the fruitless industry to account
for the ill appearances of nature, and save the honour of the gods; while
we must acknowledge the reality of that evil and disorder, with which the
world so much abounds. The obstinate and intractable qualities of matter,
we are told, or the observance of general laws, or some such reason, is
the sole cause, which controlled the power and benevolence of Jupiter,
and obliged him to create mankind and every sensible creature so imperfect
and so unhappy. These attributes then, are, it seems, beforehand, taken
for granted, in their greatest latitude. And upon that supposition, I own
that such conjectures may, perhaps, be admitted as plausible solutions
of the ill phenomena. But still I ask; Why take these attributes for granted,
or why ascribe to the cause any qualities but what actually appear in the
effect? Why torture your brain to justify the course of nature upon suppositions,
which, for aught you know, may be entirely imaginary, and of which there
are to be found no traces in the course of nature?
The religious hypothesis, therefore, must
be considered only as a particular method of accounting for the visible
phenomena of the universe: but no just reasoner will ever presume to infer
from it any single fact, and alter or add to the phenomena, in any single
particular. If you think, that the appearances of things prove such causes,
it is allowable for you to draw an inference concerning the existence of
these causes. In such complicated and sublime subjects, every one should
be indulged in the liberty of conjecture and argument. But here you ought
to rest. If you come backward, and arguing from your inferred causes, conclude,
that any other fact has existed, or will exist, in the course of nature,
which may serve as a fuller display of particular attributes; I must admonish
you, that you have departed from the method of reasoning, attached to the
present subject, and have certainly added something to the attributes of
the cause, beyond what appears in the effect; otherwise you could never,
with tolerable sense or propriety, add anything to the effect, in order
to render it more worthy of the cause.
Where, then, is the odiousness of that
doctrine, which I teach in my school, or rather, which I examine in my
gardens? Or what do you find in this whole question, wherein the security
of good morals, or the peace and order of society, is in the least concerned?
I deny a providence, you say, and supreme
governor of the world, who guides the course of events, and punishes the
vicious with infamy and disappointment, and rewards the virtuous with honour
and success, in all their undertakings. But surely, I deny not the course
itself of events, which lies open to every one's inquiry and examination.
I acknowledge, that, in the present order of things, virtue is attended
with more peace of mind than vice, and meets with a more favourable reception
from the world. I am sensible, that, according to the past experience of
mankind, friendship is the chief joy of human life, and moderation the
only source of tranquillity and happiness. I never balance between the
virtuous and the vicious course of life; but am sensible, that, to a well-disposed
mind, every advantage is on the side of the former. And what can you say
more, allowing all your suppositions and reasonings? You tell me, indeed,
that this disposition of things proceeds from intelligence and design.
But whatever it proceeds from, the disposition itself, on which depends
our happiness or misery, and consequently our conduct and deportment in
life is still the same. It is still open for me, as well as you, to regulate
my behaviour, by my experience of past events. And if you affirm, that,
while a divine providence is allowed and a supreme distributive justice
in the universe, I ought to expect some more particular reward of the good,
and punishment of the bad, beyond the ordinary course of events; I here
find the same fallacy, which I have before endeavoured to detect. You persist
in imagining, that, if we grant that divine existence, for which you so
earnestly contend, you may safely infer consequences from it, and add something
to the experienced order of nature, by arguing from the attributes which
you ascribe to your gods. You seem not to remember, that all your reasonings
on this subJect can only be drawn from effects to causes; and that every
argument, deducted from causes to effects, must of necessity be a gross
sophism; since it is impossible for you to know anything of the cause,
but what you have antecedently, not inferred, but discovered to the full,
in the effect.
But what must a philosopher think of those
vain reasoners, who instead of regarding the present scene of things as
the sole object of their contemplation, so far reverse the whole course
of nature, as to render this life merely a passage to something farther;
a porch, which leads to a greater, and vastly different building; a prologue,
which serves only to introduce the piece, and give it more grace and propriety?
Whence, do you think, can such philosophers derive their idea of the gods?
From their own conceit and imagination surely. For if they derived it from
the present phenomena, it would never point to anything farther, but must
be exactly adjusted to them. That the divinity may possibly be endowed
with attributes, which we have never seen exerted; may be governed by principles
of action, which we cannot discover to be satisfied: all this will freely
be allowed. But still this is mere possibility and hypothesis. We never
can have reason to infer any attributes, or any principles of action in
him, but so far as we know them to have been exerted and satisfied.
Are there any marks of a distributive justice
in the world? If you answer in the affirmative, I conclude, that, since
justice here exerts itself, it is satisfied. If you reply in the negative,
I conclude, that you have then no reason to ascribe justice, in our sense
of it, to the gods. If you hold a medium between affirmation and negation,
by saying, that the justice of the gods, at present, exerts itself in part,
but not in its full extent; I answer, that you have no reason to give it
any particular extent, but only so far as you see it, at present, exert
itself.
Thus I bring the dispute, O Athenians,
to a short issue with my antagonists. The course of nature lies open to
my contemplation as well as to theirs. The experienced train of events
is the great standard, by which we all regulate our conduct. Nothing else
can be appealed to in the field, or in the senate. Nothing else ought ever
to be heard of in the school, or in the closet. In vain would our limited
understanding break through those boundaries, which are too narrow for
our fond imagination. While we argue from the course of nature, and infer
a particular intelligent cause, which first bestowed, and still preserves
order in the universe, we embrace a principle, which is both uncertain
and useless. It is uncertain; because the subject lies entirely beyond
the reach of human experience. It is useless; because our knowledge of
this cause being derived entirely from the course of nature, we can never,
according to the rules of just reasoning, return back from the cause with
any new inference, or making additions to the common and experienced course
of nature, establish any new principles of conduct and behaviour.
I observe (said I, finding he had finished
his harangue) that you neglect not the artifice of the demagogues of old;
and as you were pleased to make me stand for the people, you insinuate
yourself into my favour by embracing those principles, to which, you know,
I have always expressed a particular attachment. But allowing you to make
experience (as indeed I think you ought) the only standard of our judgement
concerning this, and all other questions of fact; I doubt not but, from
the very same experience, to which you appeal, it may be possible to refute
this reasoning, which you have put into the mouth of Epicurus. If you saw,
for instance, a half-finished building, surrounded with heaps of brick
and stone and mortar, and all the instruments of masonry; could you not
infer from the effect, that it was a work of design and contrivance? And
could you not return again, from this inferred cause, to infer new additions
to the effect, and conclude, that the building would soon be finished,
and receive all the further improvements, which art could bestow upon it?
If you saw upon the sea-shore the print of one human foot, you would conclude,
that a man had passed that way, and that he had also left the traces of
the other foot, though effaced by the rolling of the sands or inundation
of the waters. Why then do you refuse to admit the same method of reasoning
with regard to the order of nature? Consider the world and the present
life only as an imperfect building, from which you can infer a superior
intelligence; and arguing from that superior intelligence, which can leave
nothing imperfect; why may you not infer a more finished scheme or plan,
which will receive its completion in some distant point of space or time?
Are not these methods of reasoning exactly similar? And under what pretence
can you embrace the one, while you reject the other?
The infinite difference of the subjects,
replied he, is a sufficient foundation for this difference in my conclusions.
In works of human art and contrivance, it is allowable to advance from
the effect to the cause, and returning back from the cause, to form new
inferences concerning the effect, and examine the alterations, which it
has probably undergone, or may still undergo. But what is the foundation
of this method of reasoning? Plainly this; that man is a being, whom we
know by experience, whose motives and designs we are acquainted with, and
whose projects and inclinations have a certain connexion and coherence,
according to the laws which nature has established for the government of
such a creature. When, therefore, we find, that any work has proceeded
from the skill and industry of man; as we are otherwise acquainted with
the nature of the animal, we can draw a hundred inferences concerning what
may be expected from him; and these inferences will all be founded in experience
and observation. But did we know man only from the single work or production
which we examine, it were impossible for us to argue in this manner; because
our knowledge of all the qualities, which we ascribe to him, being in that
case derived from the production, it is impossible they could point to
anything farther, or be the foundation of any new inference. The print
of a foot in the sand can only prove, when considered alone, that there
was some figure adapted to it, by which it was produced: but the print
of a human foot proves likewise, from our other experience, that there
was probably another foot, which also left its impression, though effaced
by time or other accidents. Here we mount from the effect to the cause;
and descending again from the cause, infer alterations in the effect; but
this is not a continuation of the same simple chain of reasoning. We comprehend
in this case a hundred other experiences and observations, concerning the
usual figure and members of that species of animal, without which this
method of argument must be considered as fallacious and sophistical.
The case is not the same with our reasonings
from the works of nature. The Deity is known to us only by his productions,
and is a single being in the universe, not comprehended under any species
or genus, from whose experienced attributes or qualities, we can, by analogy,
infer any attribute or quality in him. As the universe shews wisdom and
goodness, we infer wisdom and goodness. As it shews a particular degree
of these perfections, we infer a particular degree of them, precisely adapted
to the effect which we examine. But farther attributes or farther degrees
of the same attributes, we can never be authorised to infer or suppose,
by any rules of just reasoning. Now, without some such licence of supposition,
it is impossible for us to argue from the cause, or infer any alteration
in the effect, beyond what has immediately fallen under our observation.
Greater good produced by this Being must still prove a greater degree of
goodness: a more impartial distribution of rewards and punishments must
proceed from a greater regard to justice and equity. Every supposed addition
to the works of nature makes an addition to the attributes of the Author
of nature; and consequently, being entirely unsupported by any reason or
argument, can never be admitted but as mere conjecture and hypothesis.[4]
The great source of our mistake in this
subject, and of the unbounded licence of conjecture, which we indulge,
is, that we tacitly consider ourselves, as in the place of the Supreme
Being, and conclude, that he will, on every occasion, observe the same
conduct, which we ourselves, in his situation, would have embraced as reasonable
and eligible. But, besides that the ordinary course of nature may convince
us, that almost everything is regulated by principles and maxims very different
from ours; besides this, I say, it must evidently appear contrary to all
rules of analogy to reason, from the intentions and projects of men, to
those of a Being so different, and so much superior. In human nature, there
is a certain experienced coherence of designs and inclinations; so that
when, from any fact, we have discovered one intention of any man, it may
often be reasonable, from experience, to infer another, and draw a long
chain of conclusions concerning his past or future conduct. But this method
of reasoning can never have place with regard to a Being, so remote and
incomprehensible, who bears much less analogy to any other being in the
universe than the sun to a waxen taper, and who discovers himself only
by some faint traces or outlines, beyond which we have no authority to
ascribe to him any attribute or perfection. What we imagine to be a superior
perfection, may really be a defect. Or were it ever so much a perfection,
the ascribing of it to the Supreme Being, where it appears not to have
been really exerted, to the full, in his works, savours more of flattery
and panegyric, than of just reasoning and sound philosophy. All the philosophy,
therefore, in the world, and all the religion, which is nothing but a species
of philosophy, will never be able to carry us beyond the usual course of
experience, or give us measures of conduct and behaviour different from
those which are furnished by reflections on common life. No new fact can
ever be inferred from the religious hypothesis; no event foreseen or foretold;
no reward or punishment expected or dreaded, beyond what is already known
by practice and observation. So that my apology for Epicurus will still
appear solid and satisfactory; nor have the political interests of society
any connexion with the philosophical disputes concerning metaphysics and
religion.
There is still one circumstance, replied
I, which you seem to have overlooked. Though I should allow your premises,
I must deny your conclusion. You conclude, that religious doctrines and
reasonings can have no influence on life, because they ought to have no
influence; never considering, that men reason not in the same manner you
do, but draw many consequences from the belief of a divine Existence, and
suppose that the Deity will inflict punishments on vice, and bestow rewards
on virtue, beyond what appear in the ordinary course of nature. Whether
this reasoning of theirs be just or not, is no matter. Its influence on
their life and conduct must still be the same. And those, who attempt to
disabuse them of such prejudices, may, for aught I know, be good reasoners,
but I cannot allow them to be good citizens and politicians; since they
free men from one restraint upon their passions, and make the infringement
of the laws of society, in one respect, more easy and secure.
After all, I may, perhaps, agree to your
general conclusion in favour of liberty, though upon different premises
from those, on which you endeavour to found it. I think, that the state
ought to tolerate every principle of philosophy; nor is there an instance,
that any government has suffered in its political interests by such indulgence.
There is no enthusiasm among philosophers; their doctrines are not very
alluring to the people; and no restraint can be put upon their reasonings,
but what must be of dangerous consequence to the sciences, and even to
the state, by paving the way for persecution and oppression in points,
where the generality of mankind are more deeply interested and concerned.
But there occurs to me (continued I) with
regard to your main topic, a difficulty, which I shall just propose to
you without insisting on it; lest it lead into reasonings of too nice and
delicate a nature. In a word, I much doubt whether it be possible for a
cause to be known only by its effect (as you have all along supposed) or
to be of so singular and particular a nature as to have no parallel and
no similarity with any other cause or object, that has ever fallen under
our observation. It is only when two species of objects are found to be
constantly conjoined, that we can infer the one from the other; and were
an effect presented, which was entirely singular, and could not be comprehended
under any known species, I do not see, that we could form any conjecture
or inference at all concerning its cause. If experience and observation
and analogy be, indeed, the only guides which we can reasonably follow
in inferences of this nature; both the effect and cause must bear a similarity
and resemblance to other effects and causes, which we know, and which we
have found, in many instances, to be conjoined with each other. I leave
it to your own reflection to pursue the consequences of this principle.
I shall just observe, that, as the antagonists of Epicurus always suppose
the universe, an effect quite singular and unparalleled, to be the proof
of a Deity, a cause no less singular and unparalleled; your reasonings,
upon that supposition, seem, at least, to merit our attention. There is,
I own, some difficulty, how we can ever return from the cause to the effect,
and, reasoning from our ideas of the former, infer any alteration on the
latter, or any, addition to it.
[1] Luciani, [3 greek words].
[2] Luciani, [greek word].
[3] Luciani and Dio.
[4] In general, it may, I think, Be established
as a maxim, that where any cause is known only by its particular effects,
it must be impossible to infer any new effects from that cause; since the
qualities, which are requisite to produce these new effects along with
the former, must either be different, or superior, or of more extensive
operation, than those which simply produced the effect, whence alone the
cause is supposed to be known to us. We can never, therefore, have any
reason to suppose the existence of these qualities. To say, that the new
effects proceed only from a continuation of the same energy, which is already
known from the first effects, will not remove the difficulty. For even
granting this to be the case (which can seldom be supposed), the very continuation
and exertion of a like energy (for it is impossible it can be absolutely
the same), I say, this exertion of a like energy, in a different period
of space and time, is a very arbitrary supposition, and what there cannot
possibly be any traces of it in the effects, from which all our knowledge
of the cause is originally derived. Let the inferred cause be exactly proportioned
(as it should be) to the known effect; and it is impossible that it can
possess any qualities, from which new or different effects can be inferred.
SECTION XII: OF THE
ACADEMICAL OR SCEPTICAL PHILOSOPHY
PART I
THERE is not a greater number of philosophical
reasonings, displayed upon any subject, than those, which prove the existence
of a Deity, and refute the fallacies of Atheists; and yet the most religious
philosophers still dispute whether any man can be so blinded as to be a
speculative atheist. How shall we reconcile these contradictions? The knights
errant, who wandered about to clear the world of dragons and giants, never
entertained the least doubt with regard to the existence of these monsters.
The Sceptic is another enemy of religion,
who naturally provokes the indignation of all divines and graver philosophers;
though it is certain, that no man ever met with any such absurd creature,
or conversed with a man, who had no opinion or principle concerning any
subject, either of action or speculation. This begets a very natural question;
What is meant by a sceptic? And how far it is possible to push these philosophical
principles of doubt and uncertainty?
There is a species of scepticism, antecedent
to all study and philosophy, which is much inculcated by Des Cartes and
others, as a sovereign preservative against error and precipitate judgement.
It recommends an universal doubt, not only of all our former opinions and
principles, but also of our very faculties; of whose veracity, say they,
we must assure ourselves, by a chain of reasoning, deduced from some original
principle, which cannot possibly be fallacious or deceitful. But neither
is there any such original principle, which has a prerogative above others,
that are self-evident and convincing: or if there were, could we advance
a step beyond it, but by the use of those very faculties, of which we are
supposed to be already diffident. The Cartesian doubt, therefore, were
it ever possible to be attained by any human creature (as it plainly is
not) would be entirely incurable; and no reasoning could ever bring us
to a state of assurance and conviction upon any subject.
It must, however, be confessed, that this
species of scepticism, when more moderate, may be understood in a very
reasonable sense, and is a necessary preparative to the study of philosophy,
by preserving a proper impartiality in our judgements, and weaning our
mind from all those prejudices, which we may have imbibed from education
or rash opinion. To begin with clear and self-evident principles, to advance
by timorous and sure steps, to review frequently our conclusions, and examine
accurately all their consequences; though by these means we shall make
both a slow and a short progress in our systems; are the only methods,
by which we can ever hope to reach truth, and attain a proper stability
and certainty in our determinations.
There is another species of scepticism,
consequent to science and enquiry, when men are supposed to have discovered,
either the absolute fallaciousness of their mental faculties, or their
unfitness to reach any fixed determination in all those curious subjects
of speculation, about which they are commonly employed. Even our very senses
are brought into dispute, by a certain species of philosophers; and the
maxims of common life are subjected to the same doubt as the most profound
principles or conclusions of metaphysics and theology. As these paradoxical
tenets (if they may be called tenets) are to be met with in some philosophers,
and the refutation of them in several, they naturally excite our curiosity,
and make us enquire into the arguments, on which they may be founded.
I need not insist upon the more trite topics,
employed by the sceptics in all ages, against the evidence of sense; such
as those which are derived from the imperfection and fallaciousness of
our organs, on numberless occasions; the crooked appearance of an oar in
water; the various aspects of objects, according to their different distances;
the double images which arise from the pressing one eye; with many other
appearances of a like nature. These sceptical topics, indeed, are only
sufficient to prove, that the senses alone are not implicitly to be depended
on; but that we must correct their evidence by reason, and by considerations,
derived from the nature of the medium, the distance of the object, and
the disposition of the organ, in order to render them, within their sphere,
the proper criteria of truth and falsehood. There are other more profound
arguments against the senses, which admit not of so easy a solution.
It seems evident, that men are carried,
by a natural instinct or prepossession, to repose faith in their senses;
and that, without any reasoning, or even almost before the use of reason,
we always suppose an external universe, which depends not on our perception,
but would exist, though we and every sensible creature were absent or annihilated.
Even the animal creation are governed by a like opinion, and preserve this
belief of external objects, in all their thoughts, designs, and actions.
It seems also evident, that, when men follow
this blind and powerful instinct of nature, they always suppose the very
images, presented by the senses, to be the external objects, and never
entertain any suspicion, that the one are nothing but representations of
the other. This very table, which we see white, and which we feel hard,
is believed to exist, independent of our perception, and to be something
external to our mind, which perceives it. Our presence bestows not being
on it: our absence does not annihilate it. It preserves its existence uniform
and entire, independent of the situation of intelligent beings, who perceive
or contemplate it.
But this universal and primary opinion
of all men is soon destroyed by the slightest philosophy, which teaches
us, that nothing can ever be present to the mind but an image or perception,
and that the senses are only the inlets, through which these images are
conveyed, without being able to produce any immediate intercourse between
the mind and the object. The table, which we see, seems to diminish, as
we remove farther from it: but the real table, which exists independent
of us, suffers no alteration: it was, therefore, nothing but its image,
which was present to the mind. These are the obvious dictates of reason;
and no man, who reflects, ever doubted, that the existences, which we consider,
when we say, this house and that tree, are nothing but perceptions in the
mind, and fleeting copies or representations of other existences, which
remain uniform and independent.
So far, then, are we necessitated by reasoning
to contradict or depart from the primary instincts of nature, and to embrace
a new system with regard to the evidence of our senses. But here philosophy
finds herself extremely embarrassed, when she would justify this new system,
and obviate the cavils and objections of the sceptics. She can no longer
plead the infallible and irresistible instinct of nature: for that led
us to a quite different system, which is acknowledged fallible and even
erroneous. And to justify this pretended philosophical system, by a chain
of clear and convincing argument, or even any appearance of argument, exceeds
the power of all human capacity.
By what argument can it be proved, that
the perceptions of the mind must be caused by external objects, entirely
different from them, though resembling them (if that be possible) and could
not arise either from the energy of the mind itself, or from the suggestion
of some invisible and unknown spirit, or from some other cause still more
unknown to us? It is acknowledged, that, in fact, many of these perceptions
arise not from anything external, as in dreams, madness, and other diseases.
And nothing can be more inexplicable than the manner, in which body should
so operate upon mind as ever to convey an image of itself to a substance,
supposed of so different, and even contrary a nature.
It is a question of fact, whether the perceptions
of the senses be produced by external objects, resembling them: how shall
this question be determined? By experience surely; as all other questions
of a like nature. But here experience is, and must be entirely silent.
The mind has never anything present to it but the perceptions, and cannot
possibly reach any experience of their connexion with objects. The supposition
of such a connexion is, therefore, without any foundation in reasoning.
To have recourse to the veracity of the
supreme Being, in order to prove the veracity of our senses, is surely
making a very unexpected circuit. If his veracity were at all concerned
in this matter, our senses would be entirely infallible; because it is
not possible that he can ever deceive. Not to mention, that, if the external
world be once called in question, we shall be at a loss to find arguments,
by which we may prove the existence of that Being or any of his attributes.
This is a topic, therefore, in which the
profounder and more philosophical sceptics will always triumph, when they
endeavour to introduce an universal doubt into all subjects of human knowledge
and enquiry. Do you follow the instincts and propensities of nature, may
they say, in assenting to the veracity of sense? But these lead you to
believe that the very perception or sensible image is the external object.
Do you disclaim this principle, in order to embrace a more rational opinion,
that the perceptions are only representations of something external? You
here depart from your natural propensities and more obvious sentiments;
and yet are not able to satisfy your reason, which can never find any convincing
argument from experience to prove, that the perceptions are connected with
any external objects.
There is another sceptical topic of a like
nature, derived from the most profound philosophy; which might merit our
attention, were it requisite to dive so deep, in order to discover arguments
and reasonings, which can so little serve to any serious purpose. It is
universally allowed by modern enquirers, that all the sensible qualities
of objects, such as hard, soft, hot, cold, white, black, &c. are merely
secondary, and exist not in the objects themselves, but are perceptions
of the mind, without any external archetype or model, which they represent.
If this be allowed, with regard to secondary qualities, it must also follow,
with regard to the supposed primary qualities of extension and solidity;
nor can the latter be any more entitled to that denomination than the former.
The idea of extension is entirely acquired from the senses of sight and
feeling; and if all the qualities, perceived by the senses, be in the mind,
not in the object, the same conclusion must reach the idea of extension,
which is wholly dependent on the sensible ideas or the ideas of secondary
qualities. Nothing can save us from this conclusion, but the asserting,
that the ideas of those primary qualities are attained by Abstraction,
an opinion, which, if we examine it accurately, we shall find to be unintelligible,
and even absurd. An extension, that is neither tangible nor visible, cannot
possibly be conceived: and a tangible or visible extension, which is neither
hard nor soft, black nor white, is equally beyond the reach of human conception.
Let any man try to conceive a triangle in general, which is neither Isosceles
nor Scalenum, nor has any particular length or proportion of sides; and
he will soon perceive the absurdity of all the scholastic notions with
regard to abstraction and general ideas.[1]
Thus the first philosophical objection
to the evidence of sense or to the opinion of external existence consists
in this, that such an opinion, if rested on natural instinct, is contrary
to reason, and if referred to reason, is contrary to natural instinct,
and at the same time carries no rational evidence with it, to convince
an impartial enquirer. The second objection goes farther, and represents
this opinion as contrary to reason: at least, if it be a principle of reason,
that all sensible qualities are in the mind, not in the object. Bereave
matter of all its intelligible qualities, both primary and secondary, you
in a manner annihilate it, and leave only a certain unknown, inexplicable
something, as the cause of our perceptions; a notion so imperfect, that
no sceptic will think it worth while to contend against it.
PART II
IT may seem a very extravagant attempt of
the sceptics to destroy reason by argument and ratiocination; yet is this
the grand scope of all their enquiries and disputes. They endeavour to
find objections, both to our abstract reasonings, and to those which regard
matter of fact and existence.
The chief objection against all abstract
reasonings is derived from the ideas of space and time; ideas, which, in
common life and to a careless view, are very clear and intelligible, but
when they pass through the scrutiny of the profound sciences (and they
are the chief object of these sciences) afford principles, which seem full
of absurdity and contradiction. No priestly dogmas, invented on purpose
to tame and subdue the rebellious reason of mankind, ever shocked common
sense more than the doctrine of the infinitive divisibility of extension,
with its consequences; as they are pompously displayed by all geometricians
and metaphysicians, with a kind of triumph and exultation. A real quantity,
infinitely less than any finite quantity, containing quantities infinitely
less than itself, and so on in infinitum; this is an edifice so bold and
prodigious, that it is too weighty for any pretended demonstration to support,
because it shocks the clearest and most natural principles of human reason.[2]
But what renders the matter more extraordinary, is, that these seemingly
absurd opinions are supported by a chain of reasoning, the clearest and
most natural; nor is it possible for us to allow the premises without admitting
the consequences. Nothing can be more convincing and satisfactory than
all the conclusions concerning the properties of circles and triangles;
and yet, when these are once received, how can we deny, that the angle
of contact between a circle and its tangent is infinitely less than any
rectilineal angle, that as you may increase the diameter of the circle
in infinitum, this angle of contact becomes still less, even in infinitum,
and that the angle of contact between other curves and their tangents may
be infinitely less than those between any circle and its tangent, and so
on, in infinitum? The demonstration of these principles seems as unexceptionable
as that which proves the three angles of a triangle to be equal to two
right ones, though the latter opinion be natural and easy, and the former
big with contradiction and absurdity. Reason here seems to be thrown into
a kind of amazement and suspence, which, without the suggestions of any
sceptic, gives her a diffidence of herself, and of the ground on which
she treads. She sees a full light, which illuminates certain places; but
that light borders upon the most profound darkness. And between these she
is so dazzled and confounded, that she scarcely can pronounce with certainty
and assurance concerning any one object.
The absurdity of these bold determinations
of the abstract sciences seems to become, if possible, still more palpable
with regard to time than extension. An infinite number of real parts of
time, passing in succession, and exhausted one after another, appears so
evident a contradiction, that no man, one should think, whose judgement
is not corrupted, instead of being improved, by the sciences, would ever
be able to admit of it.
Yet still reason must remain restless,
and unquiet, even with regard to that scepticism, to which she is driven
by these seeming absurdities and contradictions. How any clear, distinct
idea can contain circumstances, contradictory to itself, or to any other
clear, distinct idea, is absolutely incomprehensible; and is, perhaps,
as absurd as any proposition, which can be formed. So that nothing can
be more sceptical, or more full of doubt and hesitation, than this scepticism
itself, which arises from some of the paradoxical conclusions of geometry
or the science of quantity.[3]
The sceptical objections to moral evidence,
or to the reasonings concerning matter of fact, are either popular or philosophical.
The popular objections are derived from the natural weakness of human understanding;
the contradictory opinions, which have been entertained in different ages
and nations; the variations of our judgement in sickness and health, youth
and old age, prosperity and adversity; the perpetual contradiction of each
particular man's opinions and sentiments; with many other topics of that
kind. It is needless to insist farther on this head. These objections are
but weak. For as, in common life, we reason every moment concerning fact
and existence, and cannot possibly subsist, without continually employing
this species of argument, any popular objections, derived from thence,
must be insufficient to destroy that evidence. The great subverter of Pyrrhonism
or the excessive principles of scepticism is action, and employment, and
the occupations of common life. These principles may flourish and triumph
in the schools; where it is, indeed, difficult, if not impossible, to refute
them. But as soon as they leave the shade, and by the presence of the real
objects, which actuate our passions and sentiments, are put in opposition
to the more powerful principles of our nature, they vanish like smoke,
and leave the most determined sceptic in the same condition as other mortals.
The sceptic, therefore, had better keep
within his proper sphere, and display those philosophical objections, which
arise from more profound researches. Here he seems to have ample matter
of triumph; while he justly insists, that all our evidence for any matter
of fact, which lies beyond the testimony of sense or memory, is derived
entirely from the relation of cause and effect; that we have no other idea
of this relation than that of two objects, which have been frequently conjoined
together; that we have no argument to convince us, that objects, which
have, in our experience, been frequently conjoined, will likewise, in other
instances, be conjoined in the same manner; and that nothing leads us to
this inference but custom or a certain instinct of our nature; which it
is indeed difficult to resist, but which, like other instincts, may be
fallacious and deceitful. While the sceptic insists upon these topics,
he shows his force, or rather, indeed, his own and our weakness; and seems,
for the time at least, to destroy all assurance and conviction. These arguments
might be displayed at greater length, if any durable good or benefit to
society could ever be expected to result from them.
For here is the chief and most confounding
objection to excessive scepticism, that no durable good can ever result
from it; while it remains in its full force and vigour. We need only ask
such a sceptic, What his meaning is? And what he proposes by all these
curious researches? He is immediately at a loss, and knows not what to
answer. A Copernican or Ptolemaic, who supports each his different system
of astronomy, may hope to produce a conviction, which will remain constant
and durable, with his audience. A Stoic or Epicurean displays principles,
which may not be durable, but which have an effect on conduct and behaviour.
But a Pyrrhonian cannot expect, that his philosophy will have any constant
influence on the mind: or if it had, that its influence would be beneficial
to society. On the contrary, he must acknowledge, if he will acknowledge
anything, that all human life must perish, were his principles universally
and steadily to prevail. All discourse, all action would immediately cease;
and men remain in a total lethargy, till the necessities of nature, unsatisfied,
put an end to their miserable existence. It is true; so fatal an event
is very little to be dreaded. Nature is always too strong for principle.
And though a Pyrrhonian may throw himself or others into a momentary amazement
and confusion by his profound reasonings; the first and most trivial event
in life will put to flight all his doubts and scruples, and leave him the
same, in every point of action and speculation, with the philosophers of
every other sect, or with those who never concerned themselves in any philosophical
researches. When he awakes from his dream, he will be the first to join
in the laugh against himself, and to confess, that all his objections are
mere amusement, and can have no other tendency than to show the whimsical
condition of mankind, who must act and reason and believe; though they
are not able, by their most diligent enquiry, to satisfy themselves concerning
the foundation of these operations, or to remove the objections, which
may be raised against them.
PART III
THERE is, indeed, a more mitigated scepticism
or academical philosophy, which may be both durable and useful, and which
may, in part, be the result of this Pyrrhonism, or excessive scepticism,
when its undistinguished doubts are, in some measure, corrected by common
sense and reflection. The greater part of mankind are naturally apt to
be affirmative and dogmatical in their opinions; and while they see objects
only on one side, and have no idea of any counterpoising argument, they
throw themselves precipitately into the principles, to which they are inclined;
nor have they any indulgence for those who entertain opposite sentiments.
To hesitate or balance perplexes their understanding, checks their passion,
and suspends their action. They are, therefore, impatient till they escape
from a state, which to them is so uneasy: and they think, that they could
never remove themselves far enough from it, by the violence of their affirmations
and obstinacy of their belief. But could such dogmatical reasoners become
sensible of the strange infirmities of human understanding, even in its
most perfect state, and when most accurate and cautious in its determinations;
such a reflection would naturally inspire them with more modesty and reserve,
and diminish their fond opinion of themselves, and their prejudice against
antagonists. The illiterate may reflect on the disposition of the learned,
who, amidst all the advantages of study and reflection, are commonly still
diffident in their determinations: and if any of the learned be inclined,
from their natural temper, to haughtiness and obstinacy, a small tincture
of Pyrrhonism might abate their pride, by showing them, that the few advantages,
which they may have attained over their fellows, are but inconsiderable,
if compared with the universal perplexity and confusion, which is inherent
in human nature. In general, there is a degree of doubt, and caution, and
modesty, which, in all kinds of scrutiny and decision, ought for ever to
accompany a just reasoner.
Another species of mitigated scepticism
which may be of advantage to mankind, and which may be the natural result
of the Pyrrhonian doubts and scruples, is the limitation of our enquiries
to such subjects as are best adapted to the narrow capacity of human understanding.
The imagination of man is naturally sublime, delighted with whatever is
remote and extraordinary, and running, without control, into the most distant
parts of space and time in order to avoid the objects, which custom has
rendered too familiar to it. A correct Judgement observes a contrary method,
and avoiding all distant and high enquiries, confines itself to common
life, and to such subjects as fall under daily practice and experience;
leaving the more sublime topics to the embellishment of poets and orators,
or to the arts of priests and politicians. To bring us to so salutary a
determination, nothing can be more serviceable, than to be once thoroughly
convinced of the force of the Pyrrhonian doubt, and of the impossibility,
that anything, but the strong power of natural instinct, could free us
from it. Those who have a propensity to philosophy, will still continue
their researches; because they reflect, that, besides the immediate pleasure
attending such an occupation, philosophical decisions are nothing but the
reflections of common life, methodized and corrected. But they will never
be tempted to go beyond common life, so long as they consider the imperfection
of those faculties which they employ, their narrow reach, and their inaccurate
operations. While we cannot give a satisfactory reason, why we believe,
after a thousand experiments, that a stone will fall, or fire burn; can
we ever satisfy ourselves concerning any determination, which we may form,
with regard to the origin of worlds, and the situation of nature, from,
and to eternity?
This narrow limitation, indeed, of our
enquiries, is, in every respect, so reasonable, that it suffices to make
the slightest examination into the natural powers of the human mind and
to compare them with their objects, in order to recommend it to us. We
shall then find what are the proper subjects of science and enquiry.
It seems to me, that the only objects of
the abstract science or of demonstration are quantity and number, and that
all attempts to extend this more perfect species of knowledge beyond these
bounds are mere sophistry and illusion. As the component parts of quantity
and number are entirely similar, their relations become intricate and involved;
and nothing can be more curious, as well as useful, than to trace, by a
variety of mediums, their equality or inequality, through their different
appearances. But as all other ideas are clearly distinct and different
from each other, we can never advance farther, by our utmost scrutiny,
than to observe this diversity, and, by an obvious reflection, pronounce
one thing not to be another. Or if there be any difficulty in these decisions,
it proceeds entirely from the undeterminate meaning of words, which is
corrected by juster definitions. That the square of the hypothenuse is
equal to the squares of the other two sides, cannot be known, let the terms
be ever so exactly defined, without a train of reasoning and enquiry. But
to convince us of this proposition, that where there is no property, there
can be no injustice, it is only necessary to define the terms, and explain
injustice to be a violation of property. This proposition is, indeed, nothing
but a more imperfect definition. It is the same case with all those pretended
syllogistical reasonings, which may be found in every other branch of learning,
except the sciences of quantity and number; and these may safely, I think,
be pronounced the only proper objects of knowledge and demonstration.
All other enquiries of men regard only
matter of fact and existence; and these are evidently incapable of demonstration.
Whatever is may not be. No negation of a fact can involve a contradiction.
The non-existence of any being, without exception, is as clear and distinct
an idea as its existence. The proposition, which affirms it not to be,
however false, is no less conceivable and intelligible, than that which
affirms it to be. The case is different with the sciences, properly so
called. Every proposition, which is not true, is there confused and unintelligible.
That the cube root of 64 is equal to the half of 10, is a false proposition,
and can never be distinctly conceived. But that Caesar, or the angel Gabriel,
or any being never existed, may be a false proposition, but still is perfectly
conceivable, and implies no contradiction.
The existence, therefore, of any being
can only be proved by arguments from its cause or its effect; and these
arguments are founded entirely on experience. If we reason a priori, anything
may appear able to produce anything. The falling of a pebble may, for aught
we know, extinguish the sun; or the wish of a man control the planets in
their orbits. It is only experience, which teaches us the nature and bounds
of cause and effect, and enables us to infer the existence of one object
from that of another.[4] Such is the foundation of moral reasoning, which
forms the greater part of human knowledge, and is the source of all human
action and behaviour.
Moral reasonings are either concerning
particular or general facts. All deliberations in life regard the former;
as also all disquisitions in history, chronology, geography, and astronomy.
The sciences, which treat of general facts,
are politics, natural philosophy, physic, chemistry, &c. where the
qualities, causes and effects of a whole species of objects are enquired
into.
Divinity or Theology, as it proves the
existence of a Deity, and the immortality of souls, is composed partly
of reasonings concerning particular, partly concerning general facts. It
has a foundation in reason, so far as it is supported by experience. But
its best and most solid foundation is faith and divine revelation.
Morals and criticism are not so properly
objects of the understanding as of taste and sentiment. Beauty, whether
moral or natural, is felt, more properly than perceived. Or if we reason
concerning it, and endeavour to fix its standard, we regard a new fact,
to wit, the general tastes of mankind, or some such fact, which may be
the object of reasoning and enquiry.
When we run over libraries, persuaded of
these principles, what havoc must we make? If we take in our hand any volume;
of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain
any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain
any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No.
Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing but sophistry
and illusion.
[1] This argument is drawn from Dr. Berkeley;
and indeed most of the writings of that very ingenious author form the
best lessons of scepticism, which are to be found either among the ancient
or modern philosophers, Bayle not excepted. He professes, however, in his
title-page (and undoubtedly with great truth) to have composed his book
against the sceptics as well as against the atheists and free-thinkers.
But that all his arguments, though otherwise intended, are, in reality,
merely sceptical, appears from this, that they admit of no answer and produce
no conviction. Their only effect is to cause that momentary amazement and
irresolution and confusion, which is the result of scepticism.
[2] Whatever disputes there may be about
the mathematical points, we must allow that there are physical points;
that is, parts of extension, which cannot be divided or lessened, either
by the eye or imagination. These images, then, which are present to the
fancy or senses, are absolutely indivisible, and consequently must be allowed
by mathematicians to be infinitely less than any real part of extension;
and yet nothing appears more certain to reason, than that an infinite number
of them composes an infinite extension. How much more an infinite number
of those infinitely small parts of extension, which are still supposed
infinitely divisible.
[3] It seems to be not impossible to avoid
these absurdities and contradictions, if it be admitted, that there is
no such thing as abstract or general ideas, properly speaking; but that
all general ideas are, in reality, particular ones, attached to a general
term, which recalls, upon occasion, other particular ones, that resemble,
in certain circumstances, the idea, present to the mind. Thus when the
term Horse is pronounced, we immediately figure to ourselves the idea of
a black or a white animal, of a particular size or figure: But as that
term is also usually applied to animals of other colours, figures and sizes,
these ideas, though not actually present to the imagination, are easily
recalled; and our reasoning and conclusion proceed in the same way, as
if they were actually present. If this be admitted (as seems reasonable)
it follows that all the ideas of quantity, upon which mathematicians reason,
are nothing but particular, and such as are suggested by the senses and
imagination, and consequently, cannot be infinitely divisible. It is sufficient
to have dropped this hint at present, without prosecuting it any farther.
It certainly concerns all lovers of science not to expose themselves to
the ridicule and contempt of the ignorant by their conclusions; and this
seems the readiest solution of these difficulties.
[4] That impious maxim of the ancient philosophy,
Ex nihilo, nihil fit, by which the creation of matter was excluded, ceases
to be a maxim, according to this philosophy. Not only the will of the supreme
Being may create matter; but, for aught, we know a priori, the will of
any other being might create it, or any other cause, that the most whimsical
imagination can assign.
|